This file is indexed.

/usr/share/doc/anarchism/html/secC9.html is in anarchism 15.1-5.

This file is owned by root:root, with mode 0o644.

The actual contents of the file can be viewed below.

  1
  2
  3
  4
  5
  6
  7
  8
  9
 10
 11
 12
 13
 14
 15
 16
 17
 18
 19
 20
 21
 22
 23
 24
 25
 26
 27
 28
 29
 30
 31
 32
 33
 34
 35
 36
 37
 38
 39
 40
 41
 42
 43
 44
 45
 46
 47
 48
 49
 50
 51
 52
 53
 54
 55
 56
 57
 58
 59
 60
 61
 62
 63
 64
 65
 66
 67
 68
 69
 70
 71
 72
 73
 74
 75
 76
 77
 78
 79
 80
 81
 82
 83
 84
 85
 86
 87
 88
 89
 90
 91
 92
 93
 94
 95
 96
 97
 98
 99
100
101
102
103
104
105
106
107
108
109
110
111
112
113
114
115
116
117
118
119
120
121
122
123
124
125
126
127
128
129
130
131
132
133
134
135
136
137
138
139
140
141
142
143
144
145
146
147
148
149
150
151
152
153
154
155
156
157
158
159
160
161
162
163
164
165
166
167
168
169
170
171
172
173
174
175
176
177
178
179
180
181
182
183
184
185
186
187
188
189
190
191
192
193
194
195
196
197
198
199
200
201
202
203
204
205
206
207
208
209
210
211
212
213
<!DOCTYPE html>
<html>
  <head>
  <meta http-equiv="Content-Type" content="text/html; charset=utf-8" />
  <title>C.9 Would laissez-faire capitalism reduce unemployment? | Anarchist Writers</title>
  </head>
  <body>
  <div class="content clear-block">
    <h1>C.9 Would laissez-faire capitalism reduce unemployment?</h1>
<p>In order to answer this question, we must first have to point out that  "actually existing capitalism" tries to manage unemployment to ensure  a compliant and servile working class. This is done under the name of fighting "inflation" but, in reality, it about controlling wages and maintaining high profit rates for the capitalist class. Market discipline  for the working class, state protection for the ruling class, in other  words. As Edward Herman points out:</p>
<blockquote><p> <i>"Conservative economists have even developed a concept of a 'natural rate of unemployment,' a metaphysical notion and throwback to an eighteenth century vision of a 'natural order,' but with a modern apologetic twist. The natural rate is defined as the minimum unemployment level consistent  with price level stability, but, as it is based on a highly abstract model  that is not directly testable, the natural rate can only be inferred from  the price level itself. That is, if prices are going up, unemployment is  below the 'natural rate' and too low, whether the actual rate is 4, 8,  or 10 percent. In this world of conservative economics, anybody is  'voluntarily' unemployed. Unemployment is a matter of rational choice: some people prefer 'leisure' over the real wage available at going (or still lower) wage rates . . .<br>
</i></p>
<p><i>"Apart from the grossness of this kind of metaphysical legerdemain, the very concept of a natural rate of unemployment has a huge built-in  bias. It takes as granted all the other institutional factors that influence the price level-unemployment trade-off (market structures and independent pricing power, business investment policies at home and abroad, the distribution of income, the fiscal and monetary mix,  etc.) and focuses solely on the tightness of the labour market  as the controllable variable. Inflation is the main threat, the  labour market (i.e. wage rates and unemployment levels) is the  locus of the solution to the problem."</i> [<b>Beyond Hypocrisy</b>, p. 94]</p>
</blockquote>
<p>Unsurprisingly, Herman defines this "natural" rate as <i>"the rate of  unemployment preferred by the propertied classes."</i> [<b>Op. Cit.</b>, p. 156] The theory behind this is usually called the <i><b>"Non-Accelerating Inflation Rate of Unemployment"</b></i> (or NAIRU). Like many of the worse aspects of  modern economics, the concept was raised Milton Friedman in the late  1960s. At around the same time, Edmund Phelps independently developed the theory (and gained the so-called "Nobel Prize" in economics for so doing  in 2006). Both are similar and both simply repeat, in neo-classical jargon,  the insight which critics of capitalism had argued for over a century:  unemployment is a necessary aspect of capitalism for it is essential  to maintaining the power of the boss over the worker. Ironically,  therefore, modern neo-classical economics is based on a notion which  it denied for over a century (this change may be, in part, because  the ruling elite thinks it has won the class war and has, currently,  no major political and social movements it has to refute by presenting  a rosy picture of the system).</p>
<p>Friedman raised his notion of a <i>"Natural Rate of Unemployment"</i> in 1968. He rooted it in the neo-classical perspective of individual expectations  rather than, say, the more realistic notion of class conflict. His  argument was simple. There exists in the economy some <i>"natural"</i> rate associated with the real wage an ideal economy would produce (this is <i>"the level that would be ground out by the Walrasian system of general equilibrium equations,"</i> to quote him). Attempts by the government to  reduce actual unemployment below this level would result in rising  inflation. This is because there would be divergence between the actual rate of inflation and its expected rate. By lowering unemployment, bosses have to raise wages and this draws unemployed people into work (note the  assumption that unemployment is voluntary). However, rising wages were  passed on by bosses in rising prices and so the <b>real</b> wage remains the same. This eventually leads to people leaving the workforce as the real wage  has fallen back to the previous, undesired, levels. However, while the  unemployment level rises back to its <i>"natural"</i> level, inflation does  not. This is because workers are interested in real wages and, so if inflation is at, say, 2% then they will demand wage increases that take this into account. If they expect inflation to increase again then workers will demand <b>more</b>  wages to make up for it, which in turn will cause prices to rise (although Friedman downplayed that this was because <b>bosses</b> were increasing their prices to maintain profit levels). This will lead to rising inflation  <b>and</b> rising unemployment. Thus the expectations of individuals are the key.</p>
<p>For many economists, this process predicted the rise of stagflation in the 1970s and gave Friedman's Monetarist dogmas credence. However, this was because the <i>"Bastard Keynesianism"</i> of the post-war period was rooted in the same neo-classical assumptions used by Friedman. Moreover, they  had forgotten the warnings of left-wing Keynesians in the 1940s that  full unemployment would cause inflation as bosses would pass on wage  rises onto consumers. This class based analysis, obviously, did not fit in well with the panglossian assumptions of neo-classical economics. Yet  basing an analysis on individual expectations does not answer the question  whether these expectations are meet. With strong organisation and a willingness  to act, workers can increase their wages  to counteract inflation. This means that there are two main options within  capitalism. The first option is to use price controls to stop capitalists  increasing their prices. However, this contradicts the scared laws of  supply and demand and violates private property. Which brings us to the  second option, namely to break unions and raise unemployment to such levels that workers think twice about standing up for themselves. In this case, workers cannot increase their money wages and so their real wages drop.</p>
<p>Guess which option the capitalist state went for? As Friedman made clear when he introduced the concept there was really nothing <i>"natural"</i>  about the natural rate theory as it was determined by state policy:</p>
<blockquote><p> <i>"I do not mean to suggest that it is immutable and unchangeable. On the  contrary, many of the market characteristics that determine its level  are man-made and policy-made. In the United States, for example, legal  minimum wage rates . . . and the strength of labour unions all make the  natural rate of unemployment higher than it would otherwise be."</i>  [<i>"The Role of Monetary Policy,"</i> pp. 1-17, <b>American Economic Review</b>,  Vol. 68, No. 1, p. 9]
</p></blockquote>
<p>Thus the "natural" rate is really a social and political phenomenon which,  in effect, measures the bargaining strength of working people. This suggests that inflation will fall when working class people are in no position to recoup rising prices in the form of rising wages. The "Natural Rate" is, in other words, about class conflict.</p>
<p>This can be seen when the other (independent) inventor of the "natural"  rate theory won the so-called Nobel prize in 2006. Unsurprisingly, the  <b>Economist</b> magazine was cock-a-hoop. [<i>"A natural choice: Edmund Phelps  earns the economics profession's highest accolade"</i>, Oct 12th 2006] The  reasons why became clear. According to the magazine, <i>"Phelps won his  laurels in part for kicking the feet from under his intellectual  forerunners"</i> by presenting a (neo-classical) explanation for the breakdown  of the so-called <i>"Phillips curve."</i> This presented a statistical trade-off  between inflation and unemployment (<i>"unemployment was low in Britain when  wage inflation was high, and high when inflation was low"</i>). The problem  was that economists <i>"were quick -- too quick -- to conclude that  policymakers therefore faced a grand, macroeconomic trade-off"</i> in which, due to <i>"such a tight labour market, companies appease workers by offering  higher wages. They then pass on the cost in the form of dearer prices,  cheating workers of a higher real wage. Thus policy makers can engineer  lower unemployment only through deception."</i> Phelps innovation was to  argue that <i>"[e]ventually workers will cotton on,  demanding still higher wages to offset the rising cost of living. They can  be duped for as long as inflation stays one step ahead of their rising  expectations of what it will be."</i> The similarities with Friedman's idea are obvious. This meant that the <i>"stable trade-off depicted by the Phillips  curve is thus a dangerous mirage"</i> which broke down in the 1970s with the rise  of stagflation.</p>
<p>Phelps argued that there was a <i>"natural"</i> rate of unemployment,  where <i>"workers' expectations are fulfilled, prices turn out as anticipated,  and they no longer sell their labour under false pretences."</i>  This  <i>"equilibrium does not, sadly, imply full employment"</i> and so capitalism  required <i>"leaving some workers mouldering on the shelf. Given economists'  almost theological commitment to the notion that markets clear, the presence  of unemployment in the world requires a theodicy to explain it."</i> The  religious metaphor does seem appropriate as most economists (and <b>The  Economist</b>) do treat the market like a god (a theodicy is a specific branch  of theology and philosophy that attempts to reconcile the existence of evil  in the world with the assumption of a benevolent God). And, as with all  gods, sacrifices are required and Phelps’ theory is the means by which this  is achieved. As the magazine noted: <i>"in much of his work he contends that  unemployment is necessary to cow workers, ensuring their loyalty to the  company and their diligence on the job, at a wage the company can afford  to pay"</i> (i.e., one which would ensure a profit).</p>
<p>It is this theory which has governed state policy since the 1980s. In other words, government's around the world have been trying to <i>"cow workers"</i> in order to ensure their obedience (<i>"loyalty to the company"</i>). Unsurprisingly,  attempts to lower the <i>"natural rate"</i> have all involved using the state to  break the economic power of working class people (attacking unions,  increasing interest rates to increase unemployment in order to temporarily  <i>"cow"</i> workers and so on). All so that profits can be keep high in the face  of the rising wages caused by the natural actions of the market!</p>
<p>Yet it must be stressed that Friedman's and Phelps' conclusions are hardly  new. Anarchists and other socialists had been arguing since the 1840s that  capitalism had no tendency to full employment either in theory or in  practice. They have also noted how periods of full employment bolstered  working class power and harmed profits. It is, as we stressed in  <a href="secC1.html#secc15">section C.1.5</a>, the fundamental disciplinary mechanism of the system. Somewhat  ironically, then, Phelps got bourgeois economics highest prize for  restating, in neo-classical jargon, the model of the labour market  expounded by, say, Marx:</p>
<blockquote><p> <i>"If [capital’s] accumulation on the one hand increases the demand for  labour, it increases on the other the supply of workers by 'setting  them free', while at the same time the pressure of the unemployed  compels those that are employed to furnish more labour, and therefore  makes the supply of labour to a certain extent independent of the  supply of labourers. The movement of the law of supply and demand of  labour on this basis completes the despotism of capital. Thus as soon  as the workers learn the secret of why it happens that the more they work, the more alien wealth they produce . . . as soon as, by setting  up trade unions, etc., they try to organise a planned co-operation  between employed and unemployed in order to obviate or to weaken the  ruinous effects of this natural law of capitalistic production on  their class, so soon capital and its sycophant, political economy,  cry out at the infringement of the 'eternal' and so to speak 'sacred'  law of supply and demand. Every combination of employed and unemployed  disturbs the 'pure' action of this law. But on the other hand, as  soon as . . . adverse circumstances prevent the creation of an  industrial reserve army and, with it, the absolute dependence of the  working-class upon the capitalist class, capital, along with its platitudinous Sancho Panza, rebels against the 'sacred' law of supply  and demand, and tries to check its inadequacies by forcible means."</i>  [<b>Capital</b>, Vol. 1, pp. 793-4]
</p></blockquote>
<p>That the <b>Economist</b> and Phelps are simply echoing, and confirming, Marx  is obvious. Modern economics, while disparaging Marx, has integrated  this idea into its macro-economic policy recommendations by urging the  state to manipulate the economy to ensure that "inflation" (i.e. wage  rises) are under control. Economics has played its role of platitudinous  sycophant well while Phelps' theory has informed state interference  (<i>"forcible means"</i>) in the economy since the 1980s, with the expected  result that wages have failed to keep up with rising productivity and  so capital as enriched itself at the expense of labour (see  <a href="secC3.html">section C.3</a> for details). The use of Phelps' theory by capital in the class war is  equally obvious -- as was so blatantly stated by <b>The Economist</b> and  the head of the American Federal Reserve during this period:</p>
<blockquote><p> <i>"there's supporting testimony from Alan Greenspan. Several times during the late 1990s, Greenspan worried publicly that, as  unemployment drifted steadily lower the 'pool of available  workers' was running dry. The dryer it ran, the greater risk of 'wage inflation,' meaning anything more than minimal increases. Productivity gains took some of the edge of this potentially  dire threat, said Greenspan, and so did 'residual fear of job  skill obsolescence, which has induced a preference for job  security over wage gains' . . . Workers were nervous and acting as if the unemployment rate were higher than the 4% it reached in the boom. Still, Greenspan was a bit worried, because . . . if the pool stayed dry, 'Significant increases in wages, in excess of productivity growth, [would] inevitably emerge, absent the  unlikely repeal of the law of supply and demand.' Which is why Greenspan &amp; Co. raised short-term interest rates by about two points during 1999 and the first half of 2000. There was no  threat of inflation . . . nor were there any signs of rising  worker militancy. But wages were creeping higher, and the  threat of the sack was losing some of its bite."</i> [Doug Henwood, <b>After the New Economy</b>, pp. 206-7]
</p></blockquote>
<p>Which is quite ironic, given that Greenspan's role in the economy was, precisely, to <i>"repeal"</i> the <i>"law of supply and demand."</i> As one left-wing economist puts it (in a chapter correctly entitled <i>"The  Workers Are Getting Uppity: Call In the Fed!"</i>), the Federal Reverse (like all Central Banks since the 1980s) <i>"worries that if too  many  people have jobs, or if it is too easy for workers to find jobs,  there will be upward pressure on wages. More rapid wage growth can get  translated into more rapidly rising prices -- in other words, inflation.  So the Fed often decides to raise interest rates to slow the economy  and keep people out of work in order to keep inflation from increasing  and eventually getting out of control."</i> However, <i>"[m]ost people probably  do not realise that the Federal Reserve Board, an agency of the  government, intervenes in the economy to prevent it from creating too  many jobs. But there is even more to the story. When the Fed hits the  brakes to slow job growth, it is not doctors, lawyers, and CEOs who end  up without jobs. The people who lose are those in the middle and the  bottom -- sales clerks, factory workers, custodians, and dishwashers.  These are the workers who don’t get hired or get laid off when the  economy slows or goes into a recession."</i> [<b>The Conservative Nanny State</b>, p. 31] Thus the state pushes up unemployment rates to slow wage growth,  and thereby relieve inflationary pressure. The reason should be obvious:</p>
<blockquote><p> <i>"In periods of low unemployment, workers don't only gain from higher  wages. Employers must make efforts to accommodate workers' various needs,  such as child care or flexible work schedules, because they know that  workers have other employment options. The Fed is well aware of the  difficulties that employers face in periods of low unemployment. It  compiles a regular survey, called the 'Beige Book,' of attitudes  from around the country about the state of the economy. Most of  the people interviewed for the Beige Book are employers.<br>
</i></p>
<p><i>"From 1997 to 2000, when the unemployment rate was at its lowest  levels in 30 years, the Beige Book was filled with complaints that  some companies were pulling workers from other companies with offers  of higher wages and better benefits. Some Beige Books reported that  firms had to offer such non-wage benefits as flexible work hours,  child care, or training in order to retain workers. The Beige Books  give accounts of firms having to send buses into inner cities to  bring workers out to the suburbs to work in hotels and restaurants.  It even reported that some employers were forced to hire workers  with handicaps in order to meet their needs for labour. </i></p>
<p><i>"From the standpoint of employers, life is much easier when the workers  are lined up at the door clamouring for jobs than when workers have the  option to shop around for better opportunities. Employers can count on  a sympathetic ear from the Fed. When the Fed perceives too much upward  wage pressure, it slams on the brakes and brings the party to an end.  The Fed justifies limiting job growth and raising the unemployment  rate because of its concern that inflation may get out of control,  but this does not change the fact that it is preventing workers, and  specifically less-skilled workers, from getting jobs, and clamping  down on their wage growth."</i> [<b>Op. Cit.</b>, pp. 32-3]</p>
</blockquote>
<p>This has not happened by accident. Lobbying by business, as another left-wing economist stresses, <i>"is directed toward increasing their economic power"</i>  and business <i>"has been a supporter of macroeconomic policies that have  operated the economy with higher rates of unemployment. The stated justification  is that this lowers inflation, but it also weakens workers' bargaining power."</i>  Unsurprisingly, <i>"the economic consequence of the shift in the balance of power in favour of business . . . has served to redistribute income towards profits at  the expense of wages, thereby lowering demand and raising unemployment."</i> In effect, the Federal Reserve <i>"has been using monetary policy as a form of  surrogate incomes policy, and this surrogate policy has been tilted against  wages in favour of profits"</i> and so is regulating the economy <i>"in  a manner favourable to business."</i> [Thomas I. Palley, <b>Plenty  of Nothing</b>, p. 77, p. 111 and pp. 112-3] That this is done under the name of fighting inflation should not fool us:</p>
<blockquote><p><i> "Mild inflation is often an indication that workers have some bargaining  strength and may even have the upper hand. Yet, it is at exactly this  stage that the Fed now intervenes owning to its anti-inflation commitment,  and this intervention raises interest rates and unemployment. Thus, far  from being neutral, the Fed's anti-inflation policy implies siding with  business in the ever-present conflict between labour and capital over distribution of the fruits of economic activity . . . natural-rate theory  serves as the perfect cloak for a pro-business policy stance."</i>  [<b>Op. Cit.</b>, p. 110]
</p></blockquote>
<p>In a sense, it is understandable that the ruling class within capitalism desires to manipulate unemployment in this way and deflect questions  about their profit, property and power onto the state of the labour market. High prices can, therefore, be blamed on high wages rather than high profits, rents and interest while, at the same time, workers will put  up with lower hours and work harder and be too busy surviving to find the time or the energy to question the boss's authority either in theory or in practice. So managing the economy by manipulating interest rates to  increase unemployment levels when required allows greater profits to be  extracted from workers as management hierarchy is more secure. People  will put up with a lot in the face of job insecurity. As left-wing economist Thomas Balogh put it, full employment <i>"generally removes the  need for servility, and thus alters the way of life, the relationship  between classes . . . weakening the dominance of men over men, dissolving  the master-servant relation. It is the greatest engine for the attainment  by all of human dignity and greater equality."</i> [<b>The Irrelevance of  Conventional Economics</b>, p. 47]</p>
<p>Which explains, in part, why the 1960s and 1970s were marked by mass  social protest against authority rather than von Hayek's <i>"Road to  Serfdom."</i> It also explains why the NAIRU was so enthusiastically  embraced and applied by the ruling class. When times are hard, workers  with jobs think twice before standing up to their bosses and so work  harder, for longer and in worse conditions. This ensures that surplus  value is increased relative to wages (indeed, in the USA, real wages  have stagnated since 1973 while profits have grown massively). In  addition, such a policy ensures that political discussion about  investment, profits, power and so on (<i>"the other institutional  factors"</i>) are reduced and diverted because working class people are  too busy trying to make ends meet. Thus the state intervenes in the  economy to <b>stop</b> full employment developing to combat inflation and  instability on behalf of the capitalist class.</p>
<p>That this state manipulation is considered consistent with the "free market"  says a lot about the bankruptcy of the capitalist system and its defenders.  But, then, for most defenders of the system state intervention on behalf of  capital is part of the natural order, unlike state intervention (at least  in rhetoric) on behalf of the working class (and shows that Kropotkin  was right to stress that the state <b>never</b> practices "laissez-faire" with  regard to the working class -- see <a href="secD1.html">section D.1</a>). Thus neo-liberal capitalism  is based on monetary policy that explicitly tries to weaken working class  resistance by means of unemployment. If "inflation" (i.e. labour income)  starts to increase, interest rates are raised so causing unemployment and,  it is hoped, putting the plebes back in their place. In other words, the road to private serfdom has been cleared of any barriers imposed on it by the rise of the working class movement and the policies of social democracy  implemented after the Second World War to stop social revolution. This is the agenda pursued so strongly in America and Britain, imposed on the  developing nations and urged upon Continental Europe.</p>
<p>Although the aims and results of the NAIRU should be enough to condemn it out of hand, it can be dismissed for other reasons. First and foremost, this "natural" rate is both invisible and can move. This means trying to find it is impossible (although it does not stop economists trying, and then trying again when rate inflation and unemployment rates refute the first attempt, and then trying again and again). In addition, it is a fundamentally a meaningless concept -- you can prove anything with an invisible, mobile  value -- it is an non-refutable concept and so, fundamentally, non-scientific.  Close inspection reveals natural rate theory to be akin to a religious  doctrine. This is because it is not possible to conceive of a  test that could possibly falsify the theory. When predictions of the  natural rate turn out wrong (as they repeatedly have), proponents can simply assert that the natural rate has changed. That has led to the most  recent incarnation of the theory in which the natural rate is basically  the trend rate of unemployment. Whatever trend is observed is natural --  case closed.</p>
<p>Since natural rate theory cannot be tested, a sensible thing would  be to examine its assumptions for plausibility and reasonableness.  However, Milton Friedman’s early work on economic methodology blocks  this route as he asserted that realism and plausibility of assumptions  have no place in economics. With most economists blindly accepting  this position, the result is a church in which entry is conditional  on accepting particular assumptions about the working of markets. The net effect is to produce an ideology, an ideology which survives due  to its utility to certain sections of society.</p>
<p>If this is the case, and it is, then any attempts to maintain the "natural"  rate are also meaningless as the only way to discover it is to watch <b>actual</b> inflation levels and raising interest rates appropriately. Which means  that people are being made unemployed on the off-chance that the unemployment  level will drop below the (invisible and mobile) "natural" rate and harm the  interests of the ruling class (high inflation rates harms interest incomes  and full employment squeezes profits by increasing workers' power). This does not seem to bother most economists, for whom empirical evidence at the best of times is of little consequence. This is doubly true with the NAIRU,  for with an invisible, mobile value, the theory is always true after the fact  -- if inflation rises as unemployment rises, then the natural rate has  increased; if inflation falls as unemployment rises, it has fallen!  As post-Keynesian economist James K. Galbraith noted in his useful critique  of the NAIRU, <i>"as the real unemployment rate moves, the apparent NAIRU moves in its shadow"</i> and its <i>"estimates and re-estimates seem largely a response to predictive failure. We still have no theory, and no external evidence, governing the fall of the estimated NAIRU. The literature simply  observes that inflation hasn't occurred and so the previous estimate must have been too high."</i> He stresses, economists have held <i>"to a concept  in the face of twenty years of unexplained variation, predictive failure, and failure of the profession to coalesce on procedural issues."</i> [<b>Created  Unequal</b>, p. 180] Given that most mainstream economists subscribe to this  fallacy, it just shows how the "science" accommodates itself to the needs  of the powerful and how the powerful will turn to any old nonsense if  it suits their purpose. A better example of supply and demand for ideology  could not be found.</p>
<p>So, supporters of "free market" capitalism do have a point, "actually existing capitalism" has created high levels of unemployment. What <b>is</b> significant is that most supporters of capitalism consider that this  is a laissez-faire policy! Sadly, the ideological supporters of pure capitalism rarely mention this state intervention on behalf of the  capitalist class, preferring to attack trade unions, minimum wages,  welfare and numerous other "imperfections" of the labour market which,  strangely, are designed (at least in rhetoric) to benefit working class  people. Ignoring that issue, however, the question now arises, would a  "purer" capitalism create full employment?</p>
<p>First, we should point out that some supporters of "free market" capitalism  (most notably, the "Austrian" school) claim that real markets are not in  equilibrium at all, i.e. that the nature state of the economy is one of disequilibrium. As we noted in <a href="secC1.html#secc16">section C.1.6</a>, this means full employment  is impossible as this is an equilibrium position but few explicitly state  this obvious conclusion of their own theories and claim against logic that  full employment can occur (full employment, it should be stressed, has never meant 100% employment as they will always be some people looking  for a job and so by that term we mean close to 100% employment). Anarchists  agree: full employment can occur in "free market" capitalism but not for  ever nor even for long periods. As the Polish socialist economist Michal  Kalecki pointed out in regards to pre-Keynesian capitalism, <i>"[n]ot only  is there mass unemployment in the slump, but average employment throughout the cycle is considerably below the peak reached in the boom. The reserve of capital equipment and the reserve army of unemployed are typical features  of capitalist economy at least throughout a considerable part of the  [business] cycle."</i> [quoted by Malcolm C. Sawyer, <b>The Economics of Michal  Kalecki</b>, pp. 115-6]</p>
<p>It is doubtful that "pure" capitalism will be any different. This is due to  the nature of the system. What is missing from the orthodox analysis is  an explicit discussion of class and class struggle (implicitly, they are there and almost always favour the bosses). Once this is included, the  functional reason for unemployment becomes clear. It serves to discipline  the workforce, who will tolerate being bossed about much more with the fear  that unemployment brings. This holds down wages as the threat of unemployment  decreases the bargaining power of workers. This means that unemployment is  not only a natural product of capitalism, it is an essential part of it.</p>
<p>So cycles of short periods approaching full employment and followed by longer  periods of high unemployment are actually a more likely outcome of pure  capitalism than continued full employment. As we argued in sections  <a href="secC1.html#secc15">C.1.5</a>  and <a href="secC7.html#secc71">C.7.1</a> capitalism needs unemployment to function successfully and so  "free market" capitalism will experience periods of boom and slump, with  unemployment increasing and decreasing over time (as can be seen from  19th century capitalism). So as Juliet Schor, a labour economist, put it,  usually <i>"employers have a structural advantage in the labour market, because  there are typically more candidates ready and willing to endure this  work marathon [of long hours] than jobs for them to fill."</i> Under  conditions of full-employment <i>"employers are in danger of losing the  upper hand"</i> and hiring new workers <i>"suddenly becomes much more difficult.  They are harder to find, cost more, and are less experienced."</i> These  considerations <i>"help explain why full employment has been rare."</i>  Thus competition in the labour market is <i>"typically skewed in favour of employers: it is a buyers market. And in a buyer's market, it is the  sellers who compromise."</i> In the end, workers adapt to this inequality of  power and instead of getting what they want, they want what they get  (to use Schor's expression).  Under full employment this changes. In  such a situation it is the bosses who have to start compromising. And  they do not like it. As Schor notes, America <i>"has never experienced  a sustained period of full employment. The closest we have gotten is  the late 1960s, when the overall unemployment rate was under 4 percent  for four years. But that experience does more to prove the point than  any other example. The trauma caused to business by those years of a  tight labour market was considerable. Since then, there has been a  powerful consensus that the nation cannot withstand such a low rate  of unemployment."</i> Hence the support for the NAIRU to ensure that <i>"forced idleness of some helps perpetuate the forced overwork of others."</i> [<b>The Overworked American</b>, p. 71, p. 75, p. 129, pp. 75-76  and p. 76]</p>
<p>So, full employment under capitalism is unlikely to last long (nor would  full employment booms fill a major part of the business cycle). In addition, it should be stressed that the notion that capitalism naturally  stays at equilibrium or that unemployment is temporary adjustments is false, even given the logic of capitalist economics. As Proudhon argued:</p>
<blockquote><p> <i>"The economists admit it [that machinery causes unemployment]: but here they repeat their eternal refrain that, after a lapse of time, the  demand for the product having increased in proportion to the reduction in price [caused by the investment], labour in turn will come finally to  be in greater demand than ever. Undoubtedly, <b>with time,</b> the equilibrium will be restored; but I must add again, the equilibrium will be no sooner restored at this point than it will be disturbed at another, because the  spirit of invention never stops."</i> [<b>System of Economical Contradictions</b>,  pp. 200-1]
</p></blockquote>
<p>That capitalism creates permanent unemployment and, indeed, needs it  to function is a conclusion that few, if any, pro-"free market" capitalists  subscribe to. Faced with the empirical evidence that full employment is  rare in capitalism, they argue that reality is not close enough to their  theories and must be changed (usually by weakening the power of labour by  welfare "reform" and reducing "union power"). Thus reality is at fault, not  the theory (to re-quote Proudhon, <i>"Political economy -- that is, proprietary  despotism -- can never be in the wrong: it must be the proletariat."</i>  [<b>Op. Cit.</b> p. 187]) So if unemployment exists, then its because real wages  are too high, not because capitalists need unemployment to discipline  labour (see <a href="secC9.html#secc92">section C.9.2</a> for evidence that this argument is false). Or  if real wages are falling as unemployment is rising, it can only mean that  the real wage is not falling fast enough -- empirical evidence is never  enough to falsify logical deductions from assumptions!</p>
<p>(As an aside, it is one of amazing aspects of the "science" of economics  that empirical evidence is never enough to refute its claims. As the  Post-Keynesian economist Nicholas Kaldor once pointed out, <i>"[b]ut unlike  any scientific theory, where the basic assumptions are chosen on the basis of direct observation of the phenomena the behaviour of which forms the subject-matter of the theory, the basic assumptions of  economic theory are either of a kind that are unverifiable. . . or of a kind which are directly contradicted by observation."</i> [<b>Further  Essays on Applied Economics</b>, pp. 177-8])</p>
<p>Of course, reality often has the last laugh on any ideology. For example, since the late 1970s and early 1980s right-wing capitalist parties have  taken power in many countries across the world. These regimes made many  pro-free market reforms, arguing that a dose of market forces would lower  unemployment, increase growth and so on. The reality proved somewhat  different. For example, in the UK, by the time the Labour Party under  Tony Blair come back to office in 1997, unemployment (while falling) was  still higher than it had been when the last Labour government left office  in 1979 (this in spite of repeated redefinitions of unemployment by the  Tories in the 1980s to artifically reduce the figures). 18 years of labour  market reform had <b>not</b> reduced unemployment even under the new  definitions. This outcome was identical to New Zealand's neo-liberal  experiment, were its overall effect was unimpressive, to say the least:  lower growth, lower productivity and feeble real wage increases combined  with rising inequality and unemployment. Like the UK, unemployment was  still higher in 1997 than it had been in 1979. Over a decade of "flexible"  labour markets had increased unemployment (more than doubling it,  in fact, at one point as in the UK under Thatcher). It is no understatement to argue, in the words of two critics of neo-liberalism, that the <i>"performance of the world economy since capital was liberalised has been worse than when it was tightly controlled"</i> and that <i>"[t]hus far, [the] actual performance [of liberalised capitalism] has not lived up to the propaganda."</i> [Larry Elliot  and Dan Atkinson, <b>The Age of Insecurity</b>, p. 274 and p. 223]  In fact, as Palley notes, <i>"wage and income growth that would have  been deemed totally unsatisfactory a decade ago are now embraced as  outstanding economic performance."</i> [<b>Op. Cit.</b>, p. 202]</p>
<p>Lastly, it is apparent merely from a glance at the history of capitalism during its laissez-faire heyday in the 19th century that "free" competition among workers for jobs does not lead to full employment. Between 1870 and 1913, unemployment was at an average of 5.7% in the  16 more advanced capitalist countries. This compares to an average of  7.3% in 1913-50 and 3.1% in 1950-70. [Takis Fotopoulos, <i>"The Nation-State and the Market"</i>, pp. 37-80, <b>Society and Nature</b>, Vol. 2, No. 2, p. 61] If laissez-faire did lead to full employment, these figures would, surely,  be reversed.</p>
<p>As discussed above, full employment <b>cannot</b> be a fixed  feature of capitalism due to its authoritarian nature and the requirements  of production for profit. To summarise, unemployment has more to do with  private property than the wages of our fellow workers or any social safety nets working class movements have managed to pressure the ruling class to accept. However, it is worthwhile to discuss why the "free market" capitalist  is wrong to claim that unemployment within their system will not exist for  long periods of time. In addition, to do so will also indicate the poverty of their theory of, and "solution" to, unemployment and the human  misery they would cause. We do this in the <a href="secC9.html#secc91">next section</a>.</p>
<h2><a name="secc91">C.9.1 Would cutting wages reduce unemployment?</a></h2>
<p>The "free market" capitalist (i.e., neo-classical, neo-liberal or "Austrian")  argument is that unemployment is caused by the real wage of labour being  higher than the market clearing level. The basic argument is that the market for labour is like any other market and as the price of a commodity increases, the demand for it falls. In terms of labour, high prices (wages) causes lower demand (unemployment). Workers, it is claimed, are more interested in money  wages than real wages (which is the amount of goods they can buy with their  money wages). This leads them to resist wage cuts even when prices are falling,  leading to a rise in their real wages and so they price themselves out of work  without realising it. From this analysis comes the argument that if workers  were allowed to compete 'freely' among themselves for jobs, real wages would  decrease and so unemployment would fall. State intervention (e.g. unemployment  benefit, social welfare programmes, legal rights to organise, minimum wage  laws, etc.) and labour union activity are, according to this theory,  the  cause of unemployment, as such intervention and activity forces wages above  their market level and  so force employers to "let people go." The key to  ending unemployment is simple: cut wages.</p>
<p>This position was brazenly put by "Austrian" economist Murray Rothbard. He  opposed any suggestion that wages should <b>not</b> be cut as the notion that  <i>"the first shock of the depression must fall on profits and not on wages."</i>  This was <i>"precisely the reverse of sound policy since profits provide the  motive power for business activity."</i> [<b>America's Great Depression</b>, p. 188]  Rothbard's analysis of the Great Depression is so extreme it almost reads  like a satirical attack on the laissez-faire position as his hysterical  anti-unionism makes him blame unions for the depression for, apparently,  merely existing (even in an extremely weakened state) for their influence  was such as to lead economists and the President to recommend to numerous  leading corporate business men <b>not</b> to cut wages to end the depression  (wages were cut, but not sufficiently as prices also dropped as we will  discuss in the <a href="secC2.html#secc92">next section</a>). It should be noted that Rothbard takes his  position on wage cutting despite of an account of the business cycle rooted  in bankers lowering interest rates and bosses over-investing as a result  (see <a href="secC8.html">section C.8</a>). So despite not setting interest rates  nor making investment decisions, he expected working class people to pay for  the actions of bankers and capitalists by accepting lower wages! Thus  working class people must pay the price of the profit seeking activities  of their economic masters who not only profited in good times, but can  expect others to pay the price in bad ones. Clearly, Rothbard took the  first rule of economics to heart: the boss is always right.</p>
<p>The chain of logic in this explanation for unemployment is rooted in many of the key assumptions of neo-classical and other marginalist economics. A firm's demand  for labour (in this schema) is the marginal physical product of labour multiplied  by the price of the output and so it is dependent on marginal productivity theory.  It is assumed that there are diminishing returns and marginal productivity as  only this produces a downward-sloping labour demand curve. For labour, it is  assumed that its supply curve is upwards slopping. So it must be stressed that  marginal productivity theory lies at the core of "free market" capitalist theories  of output and distribution and so unemployment as the marginal product of labour  is interpreted as the labour demand curve. This enforces the viewpoint that  unemployment is caused by wages being too high as firms adjust production to  bring the marginal cost of their products (the cost of producing one more item)  into equality with the product's market-determined price. So a drop in labour costs theoretically leads to an expansion in production, producing jobs for the  "temporarily" unemployed and moving the economy toward full-employment. So, in  this theory, unemployment can only be reduced by lowering the real wages of  workers currently employed. Thus the unfettered free market would ensure that  all those who want to work at the equilibrium real wage will do so. By definition,  any people who were idle in such a pure capitalism would be voluntarily enjoying  leisure and <b>not</b> unemployed. At worse, mass unemployment would be a transitory  disturbance which will quickly disappear if the market is flexible enough and there are no imperfections in it (such as trade unions, workers' rights, minimum  wages, and so on).</p>
<p>Sadly for these arguments, the assumptions required to reach it are absurd as  the conclusions (namely, that there is no involuntary unemployment as markets  are fully efficient). More perniciously, when confronted with the reality of  unemployment, most supporters of this view  argue that it arises only because  of government-imposed rigidities and trade unions. In their "ideal" world  without either, there would, they claim, be no unemployment. Of course, it is  much easier to demand that nothing should be done to alleviate unemployment  and that workers' real wages be reduced when you are sitting in a tenured  post in academia save from the labour market forces you wish others to be  subjected to (in their own interests).</p>
<p>This perspective suffered during the Great Depression and the threat of  revolution produced by persistent mass unemployment meant that dissident  economists had space to question the orthodoxy. At the head of this  re-evaluation was Keynes who presented an alternative analysis and  solution to the problem of unemployment in his 1936 book <b>The General  Theory of Employment, Interest and Money</b> (it should be noted that the  Polish socialist economist Michal Kalecki independently developed a  similar theory a few years before Keynes but without the neo-classical baggage Keynes brought into his work).</p>
<p>Somewhat ironically, given the abuse he has suffered at the hands of the right  (and some of his self-proclaimed followers), Keynes took the assumptions of neo-classical economics on the labour market as the starting point of his  analysis. As such, critics of Keynes's analysis generally misrepresent it. For  example, right-liberal von Hayek asserted that Keynes <i>"started from the correct  insight that the regular cause of extensive unemployment is real wages that are  too high. The next step consisted in the proposition that a direct lowering of  money wages could be brought about only by a struggle so painful and prolonged  that it could not be contemplated. Hence he concluded that real wages must be  lowered by the process of lowering the value of money,"</i> i.e. by inflation. Thus  <i>"the supply of money must be so increased as to raise prices to a level where the real value of the prevailing money wage is no longer greater than the  productivity of the workers seeking employment."</i> [<b>The Constitution of Liberty</b>,  p. 280] This is echoed by libertarian Marxist Paul Mattick who presented an  identical argument, stressing that for Keynes <i>"wages were less flexible than  had been generally assumed"</i> and lowering real wages by inflation <i>"allowed for  more subtle ways of wage-cutting than those traditionally employed."</i> [<b>Marx  and Keynes</b>, p. 7]</p>
<p>Both are wrong. These arguments are a serious distortion of Keynes's argument.  While he did start by assuming the neo-classical position that unemployment was  caused by wages being too high, he was at pains to stress that even with ideally  flexible labour markets cutting real wages would <b>not</b> reduce unemployment.  As such, Keynes argued that unemployment was <b>not</b> caused by labour resisting  wage cuts or by "sticky" wages. Indeed, any "Keynesian" economist who does argue  that "sticky" wages are responsible for unemployment shows that he or she has not  read Keynes -- Chapter two of the <b>General Theory</b> critiques precisely this  argument. Taking neo-classical economists at its word, Keynes analyses what would  happen <b>if</b> the labour market were perfect and so he assumes the same model  as his neo-classical opponents, namely that unemployment is caused by wages being  too high and there is flexibility in both commodity and labour markets. As he  stressed, his <i>"criticism of the accepted [neo-]classical theory of economics  has consisted not so much in finding logical flaws in its analysis as in pointing  out that its tacit assumptions are seldom or never satisfied, with the result that  it cannot solve the economic problems of the actual world."</i> [<b>The General  Theory</b>, p. 378]</p>
<p>What Keynes did was to consider the <b>overall</b> effect of cutting wages on the economy as a whole. Given that wages make up a significant part of the  costs of a commodity, <i>"if money-wages change, one would have expected the  [neo-]classical school to argue that prices would change in almost the  same proportion, leaving the real wage and the level of unemployment  practically the same as before."</i> However, this was not the case, causing Keynes to point out that they <i>"do not seem to have realised that . . .  their supply curve for labour will shift bodily with every movement of  prices."</i> This was because labour cannot determine its own real wage as  prices are controlled by bosses. Once this is recognised, it becomes  obvious that workers do not control the cost of living (i.e., the real  wage). Therefore trade unions <i>"do not raise the obstacle to any increase  in aggregate employment which is attributed to them by the [neo-]classical  school."</i> So while workers could, in theory, control their wages by asking  for less pay (or, more realistically, accepting any wage cuts imposed by their bosses as the alternative is unemployment) they do not have any  control over the prices of the goods they produce. This means that they  have <b>no</b> control over their real wages and so <b>cannot</b> reduce unemployment  by pricing themselves into work by accepting lower wages. Given these  obvious facts, Keynes concluded that there was <i>"no ground for the belief  that a flexible wage policy is capable of continuous full employment . . .  The economic system cannot be made self-adjusting along these lines."</i>  [<b>Op. Cit.</b>, p. 12, pp. 8-9, p. 15 and p. 267] As he summarised:</p>
<blockquote><p> <i>"the contention that the unemployment which characterises a depression is due to a refusal by labour to accept a reduction of money-wages  is not clearly supported by the facts. It is not very plausible to assert that unemployment in the United States in 1932 was due either to  labour obstinately refusing to accept a reduction of money-wages or to  its demanding a real wage beyond what the productivity of the economic machine was capable of furnishing . . . Labour is not more truculent in the depression than in the boom -- far from it. Nor is its physical productivity less. These facts from experience are a <b>prima facie</b> ground for questioning the adequacy of the [neo-]classical analysis."</i>  [<b>Op. Cit.</b>, p. 9]
</p></blockquote>
<p>This means that the standard neo-classical argument was flawed. While cutting  wages may make sense for one firm, it would not have this effect throughout  the economy as is required to reduce unemployment as a whole. This is another  example of the fallacy of composition. What may work with an individual worker  or firm will not have the same effect on the economy as a whole for cutting  wages for all workers would have a massive effect on the aggregate demand for  their firms products.</p>
<p>For Keynes and Kalecki, there were two possibilities if wages were cut. One  possibility, which Keynes considered the most likely, would be that a cut in  money wages across the whole economy would see a similar cut in prices. The  net effect of this would be to leave real wages unchanged. The other assumes  that as wages are cut, prices remain prices remained unchanged or only fell  by a small amount (i.e. if wealth was redistributed from workers to their  employers). This is the underlying assumption of "free market" argument that cutting wages would end the slump. In this theory, cutting real wages would  increase profits and investment and this would make up for any decline in  working class consumption and so its supporters reject the claim that cutting  real wages would merely decrease the demand for consumer goods without  automatically increasing investment sufficiently to compensate for this.</p>
<p>However, in order make this claim, the theory depends on three critical  assumptions, namely that firms can expand production, that they will  expand production, and that, if they do, they can sell their expanded  production. This theory and its assumptions can be questioned. To do so  we will draw upon David Schweickart's excellent summary. [<b>Against  Capitalism</b>, pp. 105-7]</p>
<p>The first assumption states that it is always possible for a company to take on new workers. Yet increasing production requires more than just labour. Tools, raw materials and work space are all required in addition to new workers. If production goods and facilities are not available,  employment will not be increased. Therefore the assumption that labour  can always be added to the existing stock to increase output is plainly  unrealistic, particularly if we assume with neo-classical economics that all resources are fully utilised (for an economy operating at less than  full capacity, the assumption is somewhat less inappropriate).</p>
<p>Next, will firms expand production when labour costs decline? Hardly.  Increasing production will increase supply and eat into the excess profits resulting from the fall in wages (assuming, of course, that demand holds up in the face of falling wages). If unemployment did result in a lowering of the general market wage, companies might use the opportunity to replace their current workers or force them to take a pay cut. If this happened, neither production nor employment would increase. However, it could be argued that the excess profits would increase capital investment in the  economy (a key assumption of neo-liberalism). The reply is obvious: perhaps,  perhaps not. A slumping economy might well induce financial caution and  so capitalists could stall investment until they are convinced of the  sustained higher profitability will last.</p>
<p>This feeds directly into the last assumption, namely that the produced goods will be sold. Assuming that money wages are cut, but prices remain the same then this would be a cut in real wages. But when wages decline,  so does worker purchasing power, and if this is not offset by an increase  in spending elsewhere, then total demand will decline. However, it can be  argued that not everyone's real income would fall: incomes from profits  would increase. But redistributing income from workers to capitalists, a  group who tend to spend a smaller portion of their income on consumption  than do workers, could reduce effective demand and increase unemployment.  Moreover, business does not (cannot) instantaneously make use of the  enlarged funds resulting from the shift of wages to profit for investment  (either because of financial caution or lack of existing facilities). In addition, which sane company would increase investment in the face of  falling demand for its products? So when wages decline, so does workers'  purchasing power and this is unlikely to be offset by an increase in  spending elsewhere. This will lead to a reduction in aggregate demand as  profits are accumulated but unused, so leading to stocks of unsold goods  and renewed price reductions. This means that the cut in real wages will  be cancelled out by price cuts to sell unsold stock and unemployment remains.   In  other words, contrary to neo-classical economics, a fall in wages may  result in the same or even more unemployment as aggregate demand drops  and companies cannot find a market for their goods. And so, <i>"[i]f prices  do not fall, it is still worse, for then real wages are reduced and  unemployment is increased directly by the fall in the purchase of  consumption goods."</i> [Joan Robinson, <b>Further Contributions to Economics</b>,  p. 34]</p>
<p>The "Pigou" (or <i>"real balance"</i>) effect is another neo-classical argument  that aims to prove that (in the end) capitalism will pass from slump to boom quickly. This theory argues that when unemployment is sufficiently  high, it will lead to the price level falling which would lead to a rise  in the real value of the money supply and so increase the real value  of savings. People with such assets will have become richer and this  increase in wealth will enable people to buy more goods and so investment  will begin again. In this way, slump passes to boom naturally.</p>
<p>However, this argument is flawed in many ways. In reply, Michal Kalecki  argued that, firstly, Pigou had <i>"assumed that the banking system would  maintain the stock of money constant in the face of declining incomes,  although there was no particular reason why they should."</i> If the money stock changes, the value of money will also change. Secondly, that <i>"the  gain in money holders when prices fall is exactly offset by the loss to  money providers. Thus, whilst the real value of a deposit in bank  account rises for the depositor when prices fell, the liability  represented by that deposit for the bank also rises in size."</i> And,  thirdly, <i>"that falling prices and wages would mean that the real value  of outstanding debts would be increased, which borrowers would find it  increasingly difficult to repay as their real income fails to keep pace  with the rising real value of debt. Indeed, when the falling prices and  wages are generated by low levels of demand, the aggregate real income  will be low. Bankruptcies follow, debts cannot be repaid, and a  confidence crisis was likely to follow."</i> In other words, debtors may  cut back on spending more than creditors would increase it and so the  depression would continue as demand did not rise. [Malcolm C. Sawyer,  <b>The Economics of Michal Kalecki</b>, p. 90]</p>
<p>So, the traditional neo-classical reply that investment spending will increase because lower costs will mean greater profits, leading to greater savings, and ultimately, to greater investment is weak. Lower costs will mean greater  profits only if the products are sold, which they might not be if demand  is adversely affected. In other words, a higher profit margins do not result  in higher profits due to fall in consumption caused by the reduction of  workers purchasing power. And, as Michal Kalecki argued, wage cuts in  combating a slump may be ineffective because gains in profits are not  applied immediately to increase investment and the reduced purchasing power  caused by the wage cuts causes a fall in sales, meaning that higher profit margins do not result in higher profits. Moreover, as Keynes pointed out long  ago, the forces and motivations governing saving are quite distinct from  those governing investment. Hence there is no necessity for the two quantities  always to coincide. So firms that have reduced wages may not be able to sell  as much as before, let alone more. In that case they will cut production,  add to unemployment and further reduce demand. This can set off a  vicious downward spiral of falling demand and plummeting production leading  to depression, a process described by Kropotkin (nearly 40 years before  Keynes made the same point in <b>The General Theory</b>):</p>
<blockquote><p> <i>"Profits being the basis of capitalist industry, low profits explain all ulterior consequences.<br>
</i></p>
<p><i>"Low profits induce the employers to reduce the wages, or the number of workers, or the number of days of employment during the week. . . As Adam Smith said, low profits ultimately mean a reduction of wages, and  low wages mean a reduced consumption by the worker. Low profits mean also  a somewhat reduced consumption by the employer; and both together mean  lower profits and reduced consumption with that immense class of middlemen which has grown up in manufacturing countries, and that, again, means a further reduction of profits for the employers."</i> [<b>Fields, Factories  and Workshops Tomorrow</b>, p. 33]</p>
</blockquote>
<p>So, as is often the case, Keynes was simply including into mainstream economics perspectives which had long been held by critics of capitalism and dismissed by the orthodoxy. Keynes' critique of Say's Law essentially repeated Marx's while Proudhon pointed out in 1846 that <i>"if the producer earns less, he will  buy less"</i> and this will <i>"engender . . . over-production and destitution."</i>  This was because <i>"though the workmen cost [the capitalist] something, they  are [his] customers: what will you do with your products, when driven away  by [him], they shall consume no longer?"</i> This means that cutting wages and  employment would not work for they are <i>"not slow in dealing employers a  counter-blow; for if production excludes consumption, it is soon obliged  to stop itself."</i> [<b>System of Economical Contradictions</b>, p. 204 and p. 190] Significantly, Keynes praised Proudhon's follower Silvio Gesell for getting part of the answer and for producing  <i>"an anti-Marxian socialism"</i> which the <i>"future will learn more from"</i> than Marx. [<b>Op. Cit.</b>, p. 355]</p>
<p>So far our critique of the "free market" position has, like Keynes's,  been within the assumptions of that theory itself. More has to be said,  though, as its assumptions are deeply flawed and unrealistic. It should  be stressed that while Keynes's acceptance of much of the orthodoxy ensured  that at least some of his ideas become part of the mainstream,  Post-Keynesians like Joan Robinson would latter bemoan the fact that  he sought a compromise rather than clean break with the orthodoxy. This  lead to the rise of the post-war neo-classical synthesis, the so-called  "Keynesian" argument that unemployment was caused by wages being "sticky"  and the means by which the right could undermine social Keynesianism and  ensure a return to neo-classical orthodoxy.</p>
<p>Given the absurd assumptions underlying the "free market" argument, a wider  critique is possible as it reflects reality no more than any other part of  the pro-capitalist ideology which passes for mainstream economics.</p>
<p>As noted above, the argument that unemployment is caused by wages being too high is part of the wider marginalist perspective. Flaws in that will  mean that its explanation of unemployment is equally flawed. So it must  be stressed that the marginalist theory of distribution lies at the core  of its theories of both output and unemployment. In that theory, the marginal  product of labour is interpreted as the labour demand curve as the firm's  demand for labour is the marginal physical product of labour multiplied by  the price of the output and this produces the viewpoint that unemployment is  caused by wages being too high. So given the central role which marginal  productivity theory plays in the mainstream argument, it is useful to start  our deeper critique by re-iterating that, as indicated in <a href="secC2.html">section C.2</a>,  Joan Robinson and Piero Sraffa had successfully debunked this theory in the  1950s. <i>"Yet for psychological and political reasons,"</i> notes James K.  Galbraith, <i>"rather than for logical and mathematical ones, the capital  critique has not penetrated mainstream economics. It likely never will.  Today only a handful of economists seem aware of it."</i> [<i>"The  distribution of income"</i>, pp. 32-41, Richard P. F. Holt and Steven Pressman  (eds.), <b>A New Guide to Post Keynesian Economics</b>, p. 34] Given that this  underlies the argument that high wages cause high unemployment, it means that the mainstream argument for cutting wages has no firm theoretical basis.</p>
<p>It should also be noted that the assumption that adding more labour to capital is always possible flows from the assumption of marginal productivity theory  which treats "capital" like an ectoplasm and can be moulded into whatever form is required by the labour available (see <a href="secC2.html#secc25">section C.2.5</a> for more  discussion). Hence Joan Robinson's dismissal of this assumption, for <i>"the difference between the future and the past is eliminated by making  capital 'malleable' so that mistakes can always be undone and equilibrium  is always guaranteed. . . with 'malleable' capital the demand for labour  depends on the level of wages."</i> [<b>Contributions to Modern Economics</b>, p. 6] Moreover, <i>"labour and capital are not often as smoothly substitutable for each other as the [neo-classical] model requires . . . You can't use one without the other. You can't measure the marginal productivity of one  without the other."</i> Demand for capital and labour is, sometimes, a <b>joint</b> demand and so it is often to adjust wages to a worker's marginal productivity independent of the cost of capital. [Hugh Stretton,  <b>Economics: A New Introduction</b>, p. 401]</p>
<p>Then there is the role of diminishing returns. The assumption that the demand  curve for labour is always downward sloping with respect to aggregate employment  is rooted in the notion that industry operates, at least in the short run, under  conditions of diminishing returns. However, diminishing returns are <b>not</b> a  feature of industries in the real world. Thus the assumption that the downward  slopping marginal product of labour curve is identical to the aggregate demand  curve for labour is not true as it is inconsistent with empirical evidence.  <i>"In a system at increasing returns,"</i> noted one economist, <i>"the direct relation  between real wages and employment tends to render the ordinary mechanism of wage  adjustment ineffective and unstable."</i> [Ferdinando Targetti, <b>Nicholas Kaldor</b>,  p. 344] In fact, as discussed in <a href="secC1.html#secc12">section C.1.2</a>, without this assumption mainstream economics cannot show that unemployment is, in fact, caused by real wages being too high (along with many other things).</p>
<p>Thus, if we accept reality, we must end up <i>"denying the inevitability of a  negative relationship between real wages and employment."</i> Post-Keynesian  economists have not found any empirical links between the growth of unemployment  since the early in 1970s and changes in the relationship between productivity  and wages and so there is <i>"no theoretical reason to expect a negative  relationship between employment and the real wage, even at the level of the  individual firm."</i> Even the beloved marginal analysis cannot be used in the labour market, as <i>"[m]ost jobs are offered on a take-it-or-leave-it basis.  Workers have little or no scope to vary hours of work, thereby making marginal  trade-offs between income and leisure. There is thus no worker sovereignty  corresponding to the (very controversial) notion of consumer sovereignty."</i>  Over all, <i>"if a relationship exists between aggregate employment and the  real wage, it is employment that determines wages. Employment and unemployment  are product market variables, not labour market variables. Thus attempts to restore full employment by cutting wages are fundamentally misguided."</i> [John E. King, <i>"Labor and Unemployment,"</i> pp. 65-78, Holt and Pressman (eds.),  <b>Op. Cit.</b>, p. 68, pp. 67-8, p. 72, p. 68 and p. 72] In addition:</p>
<blockquote><p> <i>"Neo-classical theorists themselves have conceded that a negative relationship between the real wage and the level of employment can be established only in a one-commodity model; in a multi-commodity framework no such generalisation is possible. This confines neo-classical theory to an economy without money and makes it inapplicable to a capitalist or entrepreneurial economy."</i>  [<b>Op. Cit.</b>, p. 71]
</p></blockquote>
<p>And, of course, the whole analysis is rooted in the notion of perfect  competition. As Nicholas Kaldor mildly put it:</p>
<blockquote><p> <i>"If economics had been a 'science' in the strict sense of the word, the  empirical observation that most firms operate in imperfect markets would  have forced economists to scrap their existing theories and to start thinking  on entirely new lines . . . unfortunately economists do not feel under the  same compulsion to maintain a close correspondence between theoretical  hypotheses and the facts of experience."</i> [<b>Further Essays on Economic  Theory ad Policy</b>, p. 19]
</p></blockquote>
<p>Any real economy is significantly different from the impossible notion of  perfect competition and <i>"if there exists even one monopoly anywhere in the  system . . . it follows that others must be averaging less than the marginal value of their output. So to concede the existence of monopoly requires that one either drop the competitive model entirely or construct an elaborate new theory . . . that divides the world into monopolistic, competitive, and subcompetitive ('exploited') sectors."</i> [James K. Galbraith, <b>Created Unequal</b>, p. 52] As noted in <a href="secC4.html#secc43">section C.4.3</a>, mainstream economists have admitted that  monopolistic competition (i.e., oligopoly) is the dominant market form but they cannot model it due to the limitations of the individualistic assumptions of bourgeois economics. Meanwhile, while thundering against unions the  mainstream economics profession remains strangely silent on the impact of big business and pro-capitalist monopolies like patents and copyrights on distribution and so the impact of real wages on unemployment.</p>
<p>All this means that <i>"neither the demand for labour nor the supply of labour  depends on the real wage. It follows from this that the labour market is not  a true market, for the price associated with it, the wage rate, is incapable  of performing any market-clearing function, and thus variations in the wage  rate cannot eliminate unemployment."</i> [King, <b>Op. Cit.</b>, p. 65] As such, the  <i>"conventional economic analysis of markets . . . is unlikely to apply"</i>  to the labour market and as a result <i>"wages are highly unlikely to reflect  workers' contributions to production."</i> This is because economists treat  labour as no different from other commodities yet <i>"economic theory  supports no such conclusion."</i> At its most basic, labour is <b>not</b> produced  for profit and the <i>"supply curve for labour can 'slope backward' -- so  that a fall in wages can cause an increase in the supply of workers."</i> In  fact, the idea of a backward sloping supply curve for labour is just as  easy to derive from the assumptions used by economists to derive their  standard one. This is because workers may prefer to work less as the wage  rate rises as they will be better off even if they do not work more.  Conversely, very low wage rates are likely to produce a very high supply  of labour as workers need to work more to meet their basic needs. In  addition, as noted at the end of <a href="secC1.html#secc14">section C.1.4</a>, economic theory itself  shows that workers will not get a fair wage when they face very powerful  employers unless they organise unions. [Steve Keen, <b>Debunking Economics</b>,  pp. 111-2 and pp. 119-23]</p>
<p>Strong evidence that this model of the labour market can be found from  the history of capitalism. Continually we see capitalists turn to the  state to ensure low wages in order to ensure a steady supply of labour  (this was a key aim of state intervention during the rise of capitalism,  incidentally). For example, in central and southern Africa mining companies  tried to get locals to labour. They had little need for money, so they  worked a day or two then disappeared for the rest of the week. To avoid  simply introducing slavery, some colonial administrators introduced and  enforced a poll-tax. To earn enough to pay it, workers had to work a  full week. [Hugh Stretton, <b>Op. Cit.</b>, p. 403] Much the same was imposed  on British workers at the dawn of capitalism. As Stephen Marglin points  out, the <i>"indiscipline of the labouring classes, or more bluntly, their  laziness, was widely noted by eighteenth century observers."</i> By laziness  or indiscipline, these members of the ruling class meant the situation  where <i>"as wages rose, workers chose to work less."</i> In economic terms, <i>"a  backward bending labour supply curve is a most natural phenomenon as long  as the individual worker controls the supply of labour."</i> However, <i>"the  fact that higher wages led workers to choose more leisure . . . was disastrous"</i>  for the capitalists. Unsurprisingly, the bosses did not meekly accept the  workings of the invisible hand. Their <i>"first recourse was to the law"</i>  and they <i>"utilised the legislative, police and judicial powers of the  state"</i> to ensure that working class people had to supply as many hours  as the bosses demanded. [<i>"What do Bosses do?"</i>, pp. 60-112, <b>Review of  Radical Political Economy</b>, Vol. 6, No. 2, pp. 91-4]</p>
<p>This means that the market supply curve <i>"could have any shape at all"</i>  and so economic theory <i>"fails to prove that employment is determined  by supply and demand, and reinforces the real world observation that  involuntary unemployment can exist"</i> as reducing the wage need not  bring the demand and supply of labour into alignment. While the  possibility of backward-bending labour supply curves is sometimes  pointed out in textbooks, the assumption of an upward sloping supply  curve is taken as the normal situation but <i>"there is no theoretical -- or empirical -- justification for this."</i> Sadly for the world, this  assumption is used to draw very strong conclusions by economists. The  standard arguments against minimum wage legislation, trade unions and  demand management by government are all based on it. Yet, as Keen notes,  such important policy positions <i>"should be based upon robust intellectual  or empirical foundations, rather than the flimsy substrate of mere fancy.  Economists are quite prone to dismiss alternative perspectives on labour  market policy on this very basis -- that they lack any theoretical or  empirical foundations. Yet their own policy positions are based as much  on wishful thinking as on wisdom."</i> [<b>Op. Cit.</b>, pp. 121-2 and p. 123]</p>
<p>Within a capitalist economy the opposite assumption to that taken by  economics is far more likely, namely that there <b>is</b> a backward sloping  labour supply curve. This is because the decision to work is <b>not</b> one based on the choice between wages and leisure made by the individual worker. Most workers do <b>not</b> choose whether they work or not, and the  hours spent working, by comparing their (given) preferences and the  level of real wages. They do <b>not</b> practice voluntary leisure waiting for the real wage to exceed their so-called <i>"reservation"</i> wage (i.e.  the wage which will tempt them to forsake a life of leisure for the disutility of work). Rather, most workers have to take a job because  they do not have a choice as the alternative is poverty (at best) or  starvation and homelessness (at worse). The real wage influences the decision on how much labour to supply rather than the decision to work or not. This is because as workers and their families have a  certain basic living standard to maintain and essential bills which need to be paid. As earnings increase, basic costs are covered and so people are more able to work less and so the supply of labour tends to fall. Conversely, if real earnings fall because the real wage is less then  the supply of labour may <b>increase</b> as people work more hours and/or  more family members start working to make enough to cover the bills (this is because, once in work, most people are obliged to accept the hours set by their bosses). This is the opposite of what happens  in "normal" markets, where lower prices are meant to produce a  <b>decrease</b> in the amount of the commodity supplied. In other words,  the labour market is not a market, i.e. it reacts in different ways  than other markets (Stretton provides a good summary of this argument  [<b>Op. Cit.</b>, pp. 403-4 and p. 491]).</p>
<p>So, as radical economists have correctly observe, such considerations  undercut the "free market" capitalist contention that labour  unions and state intervention are responsible for unemployment (or  that depressions will easily or naturally end by the workings of the  market). To the contrary, insofar as labour unions and various welfare  provisions prevent demand from falling as low as it might otherwise  go during a slump, they apply a brake to the downward spiral. Far  from being responsible for unemployment, they actually mitigate it. For example, unions, by putting purchasing power in the hands of  workers, stimulates demand and keeps employment higher than the level  it would have been. Moreover, wages are generally spent immediately and  completely whilst profits are not. A shift from profits to wages may  stimulate the economy since more money is spent but there will be a  delayed cut in consumption out of profits. [Malcolm Sawyer, <b>The  Economics of Michal Kalecki</b>, p. 118] All this should be obvious, as  wages (and benefits) may be costs for some firms but they are revenue  for even more and labour is not like other commodities and reacts in  changes in price in different ways.</p>
<p>Given the dynamics of the labour "market" (if such a term makes much  sense given its atypical nature), any policies based on applying  "economics 101" to it will be doomed to failure. As such, any book  entitled <b>Economics in One Lesson</b> must be viewed with suspicion  unless it admits that what it expounds has little or no bearing to  reality and urges the reader to take at least the second lesson. Of  course, a few people actually do accept the simplistic arguments that  reside in such basic economics texts and think that they explain the  world (these people usually become right-"libertarians" and spend the  rest of their lives ignoring their own experience and reality in favour  of a few simple axioms). The wage-cutting argument (like most of economics)  asserts that any problems are due to people not listening to economists and that there is no economic power, there are no "special interests" -- it  is just that people are stupid. Of course, it is irrelevant that it is much  easier to demand that workers' real wages be reduced when you are sitting  in a tenured post in academia. True to their ideals and "science", it is  refreshing to see how many of these "free market" economists renounce  tenure so that their wages can adjust automatically as the market demand  for their ideologically charged comments changes.</p>
<p>So when economic theories extol suffering for future benefits, it is  always worth asking who suffers, and who benefits. Needless to say,  the labour market flexibility agenda is anti-union, anti-minimum wage,  and anti-worker protection. This agenda emerges from theoretical claims  that price flexibility can restore full employment, and it rests dubious logic, absurd assumptions and on a false analogy comparing the labour market  with the market for peanuts. Which, ironically, is appropriate as the  logic of the model is that workers will end up working for peanuts! As such, the "labour market" model has a certain utility as it removes the  problem of institutions and, above all, power from the perspective of  the economist. In fact, institutions such as unions can only be considered  as a problem in this model rather than a natural response to the unique  nature of the labour "market" which, despite the obvious differences,  most economists treat like any other.</p>
<p>To conclude, a cut in wages may deepen any slump, making it deeper and longer than it otherwise would be. Rather than being the solution to unemployment, cutting wages will make it worse (we will address the question of whether  wages being too high actually causes unemployment in the first place, in  the <a href="secC9.html#secc92">next section</a>). Given that,  as we argued in <a href="secC8.html#secc82">section C.8.2</a>, inflation  is caused by insufficient profits  for capitalists (they try to maintain their profit margins by price  increases) this spiralling effect of cutting wages helps to explain what  economists term <i>"stagflation"</i> -- rising unemployment combined with rising  inflation (as seen in the 1970s). As workers are made unemployed,  aggregate demand falls, cutting profit margins even more and in response  capitalists raise prices in an attempt to recoup their losses. Only a  very deep recession can break this cycle (along with labour militancy  and more than a few workers and their families).</p>
<p>Thus the capitalist solution to crisis is based on working class people paying  for capitalism's contradictions. For, according to the mainstream theory, when  the production capacity of a good exceeds any reasonable demand for it, the  workers must be laid off and/or have their wages cut to make the company  profitable again. Meanwhile the company executives -- the people responsible  for the bad decisions to build lots of factories -- continue to collect their  fat salaries, bonuses and pensions, and get to stay on to help manage the  company through its problems. For, after all, who better, to return a company  to profitability than those who in their wisdom ran it into bankruptcy? Strange, though, no matter how high their salaries and bonuses get,  managers and executives <b>never</b> price <b>themselves</b> out of work.</p>
<p>All this means that working class people have two options in a slump --  accept a deeper depression in order to start the boom-bust cycle again or  get rid of capitalism and with it the contradictory nature of capitalist  production which produces the business cycle in the first place (not to  mention other blights such as hierarchy and inequality). In the end,  the only solution to unemployment is to get rid of the system which  created it by workers seizing their means of production and abolishing  the state. When this happens, then production for the profit of the few  will be ended and so, too, the contradictions this generates.</p>
<h2><a name="secc92">C.9.2 Is unemployment caused by wages being too high?</a></h2>
<p>As we noted in the <a href="secC9.html#secc91">last section</a>, most capitalist economic theories argue that unemployment is caused by wages being too high. Any economics student will tell you that labour is like any other commodity and so if its price is too high then there will be less demand for it, so producing an excess supply of it on the market. Thus high wages will  reduce the quantity of labour demanded and so create unemployment -- a  simple case of "supply and demand."</p>
<p>From this theory we would expect that areas and periods with high wages  will also have high levels of unemployment. Unfortunately for the theory,  this does not seem to be the case. Even worse for it, high wages are  generally associated with booms rather than slumps and this has been known  to mainstream economics since at least 1939 when in March of that year <b>The Economic Journal</b> printed an article by Keynes about the movement of  real wages during a boom in which he evaluated the empirical analysis of  two labour economists (entitled <i>"Relative Movements of Real Wages and  Output"</i> this is contained as an Appendix of most modern editions of <b>The  General Theory</b>).</p>
<p>These studies showed that <i>"when money wages are rising, real wages have  usually risen too; whilst, when money wages are falling, real wages are  no more likely to rise than to fall."</i> Keynes admitted that in <b>The General  Theory</b> he was <i>"accepting, without taking care to check the facts"</i>, a  <i>"widely held"</i> belief. He discussed where this belief came from, namely  leading 19th century British economist Alfred Marshall who had produced a  <i>"generalisation"</i> from a six year period between 1880-86 which was not  true for the subsequent business cycles of 1886 to 1914. He also quotes  another leading economist, Arthur Pigou, from 1927 on how <i>"the upper halves of  trade cycles have, on the whole, been associated with higher rates of real  wages than the lower halves"</i> and indicates that he provided evidence on  this from 1850 to 1910 (although this did not stop Pigou reverting to the  <i>"Marshallian tradition"</i> during the Great Depression and blaming high unemployment on high wages). [<b>The General Theory</b>, p. 394, p. 398 and  p. 399] Keynes conceded the point, arguing that he had tried to minimise  differences between his analysis and the standard perspective. He stressed  that while he assumed countercyclical real wages his argument did not depend  on it and given the empirical evidence provided by labour economists he  accepted that real wages were pro-cyclical in nature.</p>
<p>The reason why this is the case is obvious given the analysis in the  <a href="secC9.html#secc91">last section</a>. Labour does not control prices and so cannot control its own real  wage. Looking at the Great Depression, it seems difficult to blame it on  workers refusing to take pay cuts when by 1933 <i>"wages and salaries in U.S.  manufacturing were less than half their 1929 levels and, in automobiles and  steel, were under 40 percent of the 1929 levels."</i> In Detroit, there had  been 475,000 auto-workers. By 1931 <i>"almost half has been laid off."</i> [William  Lazonick, <b>Competitive Advantage on the Shop Floor</b>, p. 271] The notion of  all powerful unions or workers' resistance to wage cuts causing high  unemployment hardly fits these facts. Peter Temin provides information on  real wages in manufacturing during the depression years. Using 1929 as  the base year, weekly average real wages (i.e., earnings divided by the  consumer price index) fell each year to reach a low of 85.5% by 1932.  Hourly real wages remained approximately constant (rising to 100.1%  in 1930 and then 102.6% in 1931 before falling to 99% in 1932). The  larger fall in weekly wages was due to workers having a shorter working  week. The <i>"effect of shorter hours and lower wages was to decrease the  income of employed workers."</i> Thus the notion that lowering wages will  increase employment seems as hard to support as the notion that wages being  too high caused the depression in the first place. Temin argues, <i>"no part of  the [neo-]classical story is accurate."</i> [<b>Did Monetary Forces Cause the Great  Depression?</b>, pp. 139-40] It should be noted that the consensus of economists  is that during this period the evidence seems to suggest that real wages <b>did</b>  rise overall. This was because the prices of commodities fell faster than did  the wages paid to workers. Which confirms Keynes, as he had argued that workers  cannot price themselves into work as they have no control over prices. However,  there is no reason to think that high real wages caused the high unemployment  as the slump itself forced producers to cut prices (not to mention wages).  Rather, the slump caused the increase in real wages.</p>
<p>Since then, economists have generally confirmed that real wage are procyclical. In fact, <i>"a great deal of empirical research has been conducted in this area  -- research which mostly contradicts the neo-classical assumption of an inverse  relation between real wages and employment."</i> [Ferdinando Targetti, <b>Nicholas  Kaldor</b>, p. 50] Nicholas Kaldor, one of the first Keynesians, also stressed that the notion that there is an inverse relationship between real wages and  employment is <i>"contradicted by numerous empirical studies which show that, in  the short period, changes in real wages are positively correlated with changes  in employment and not negatively."</i> [<b>Further Essays on Economic Theory and  Policy</b>, p. 114fn] As Hugh Stretton summarises in his excellent introductory text on economics:</p>
<blockquote><p> <i>"In defiance of market theory, the demand for labour tends strongly to vary  <b>with</b> its price, not inversely to it. Wages are high when there is full  employment. Wages -- especially for the least-skilled and lowest paid -- are  lowest when there is least employment. The causes chiefly run from the  employment to the wages, rather than the other way. Unemployment weakens  the bargaining power, worsens the job security and working conditions, and  lowers the pay of those still in jobs.<br>
</i></p>
<p><i>"The lower wages do not induce employers to create more jobs . . . most  business firms have no reason to take on more hands if wages decline. Only  empty warehouses, or the prospect of more sales can get them to do that,  and these conditions rarely coincide with falling employment and wages. The  causes tend to work the other way: unemployment lowers wages, and the lower  wages do not restore the lost employment."</i> [<b>Economics: A New Introduction</b>,  pp. 401-2]</p>
</blockquote>
<p>Will Hutton, the British neo-Keynesian economist, summarises research  by two other economists that suggests high wages do not cause unemployment:</p>
<blockquote><p> <i>"the British economists David Blanchflower and Andrew Oswald [examined] . . .  the data in twelve countries about the actual relation between wages and  unemployment -- and what they have discovered is another major challenge  to the free market account of the labour market. Free market theory would predict that low wages would be correlated with low local unemployment; and high wages with high local unemployment.<br>
</i></p>
<p><i>"Blanchflower and Oswald have found precisely the opposite relationship.  The higher the wages, the lower the local unemployment -- and the lower  the wages, the higher the local unemployment. As they say, this is not a  conclusion that can be squared with free market text-book theories of  how a competitive labour market should work."</i> [<b>The State We're In</b>,  p. 102]</p>
</blockquote>
<p>Unemployment was highest where real wages were lowest and nowhere had falling wages being followed by rising employment or falling unemployment. Blanchflower and Oswald stated that their conclusion is that employees  <i>"who work in areas of high unemployment earn less, other things constant,  than those who are surrounded by low unemployment."</i> [<b>The Wage Curve</b>,  p. 360] This relationship, the exact opposite of that predicted by  "free market" capitalist economics, was found in many different  countries and time periods, with the curve being similar for different  countries. Thus, the evidence suggests that high unemployment is  associated with low earnings, not high, and vice versa.</p>
<p>Looking at less extensive evidence, if minimum wages and unions cause  unemployment, why did the South-eastern states of the USA (with a <b>lower</b>  minimum wage and weaker unions) have a <b>higher</b> unemployment rate than  North-western states during the 1960s and 1970s? Or why, when the (relative)  minimum wage declined under Reagan and Bush in the 1980s, did chronic  unemployment accompany it? [Allan Engler, <b>The Apostles of Greed</b>,  p. 107] Or the <b>Low Pay Network</b> report <i>"Priced Into Poverty"</i>  which discovered that in the 18  months before they were abolished, the British Wages Councils (which  set minimum wages for various industries) saw a rise of 18,200 in  full-time equivalent jobs compared to a net loss of 39,300 full-time  equivalent jobs in the 18 months afterwards. Given that nearly half  the vacancies in former Wages Council sectors paid less than the rate  which it is estimated Wages Councils would now pay, and nearly 15%  paid less than the rate at abolition, there should (by the "free market" argument) have been rises in employment in these sectors as pay fell. The opposite happened. This research shows that the falls in pay  associated with Wages Council abolition had not created more employment.  Indeed, employment growth was more buoyant prior to abolition than  subsequently. So whilst Wages Council abolition did not result in more  employment, the erosion of pay rates caused by their abolition resulted  in more families having to endure poverty pay. Significantly, the  introduction of a national minimum wage by the first New Labour  government did not have the dire impact "free market" capitalist economists and politicians predicted.</p>
<p>It should also be noted that an extensive analysis of the impact of minimum  wage increases at the state level in America by economists David Card and  Alan Kreuger found the facts contradicted the standard theory, with rises  in the minimum wage having a small positive impact on both employment and wages for all workers. [<b>Myth and Measurement: The New Economics of the  Minimum Wage</b>] While their work was attacked by business leaders and  economists from think-tanks funded by them, Card and Kreuger's findings  that raising the lowest wages had no effect on unemployment or decreased  it proved to be robust. In particular, when replying to criticism of their  work by other economists who based their work, in part, on data supplied  by a business funded think-tank Card and Krueger discovered that not only  was that work consistent with their original findings but that the <i>"only  data set that indicates a significant decline in employment"</i> was by some  amazing coincidence <i>"the small set of  restaurants collected by"</i> the think  tank. [<i>"Minimum Wages and Employment: A Case Study of the Fast-Food  Industry in New Jersey and Pennsylvania: Reply"</i>, pp. 1397-1420, <b>The  American Economic Review</b>, Vol. 90, No. 5, p. 1419] For a good overview  of <i>"how the fast food industry and its conservative allies sought to  discredit two distinguished economists, and how the attack backfired"</i> when <i>"the two experts used by the fast food industry to impeach Card  and Krueger, effectively ratified them"</i> see John Schmitt's <i>"Behind the  Numbers: Cooked to Order."</i> [<b>The American Prospect</b>, May-June 1996,  pp. 82-85]</p>
<p>(This does not mean that anarchists support the imposition of a legal minimum wage. Most anarchists do not because it takes the responsibility for wages from unions and other working class organisations, where it belongs, and places it in the hands of the state. We mention these  examples in order to highlight that the "free market" capitalist  argument has serious flaws with it.)</p>
<p>Empirical evidence does not support the argument the "free market" capitalist  argument that unemployment is caused by real wages being too high. The  phenomenon that real wages tend to increase during the upward swing of the  business cycle (as unemployment falls) and fall during recessions (when  unemployment increases) renders the standard interpretation that real wages  govern employment difficult to maintain (real wages are <i>"pro-cyclical,"</i> to  use economic terminology). This evidence makes it harder for economists to  justify policies based on a direct attack on real wages as the means to  cure unemployment.</p>
<p>While this evidence may come as a shock to those who subscribe to the  arguments put forward by those who think capitalist economics reflect the reality of that system, it fits well with the anarchist and other socialist  analysis. For anarchists, unemployment is a means of disciplining labour  and maintaining a suitable rate of profit (i.e. unemployment is a key means  of ensuring that workers are exploited). As full employment is approached,  labour's power increases, so reducing the rate of exploitation and so  increasing labour's share of the value it produces (and so higher wages).  Thus, from an anarchist point of view, the fact that wages are higher in  areas of low unemployment is not a surprise, nor is the phenomenon of  pro-cyclical real wages. After all, as we noted in <a href="secC3.html">section C.3</a>,  the ratio  between wages and profits are, to a large degree, a product of bargaining  power and so we would expect real wages to grow in the upswing of the  business cycle, fall in the slump and be high in areas of low unemployment.</p>
<p>The evidence therefore suggests that the "free market" capitalist claim  that unemployment is caused by unions, "too high" wages, and so on, is  false. Indeed, by stopping capitalists appropriating more of the income  created by workers, high wages maintain aggregate demand and contribute  to higher employment (although, of course, high employment cannot be  maintained indefinitely under wage slavery due to the rise in workers'  power this implies). Rather, unemployment is a key aspect of the capitalist  system and cannot be got rid off within it. The "free market" capitalist  "blame the workers" approach fails to understand the nature and dynamic  of the system (given its ideological role, this is unsurprising). So  high real wages for workers increases aggregate demand and reduces  unemployment from the level it would be if the wage rate was cut. This  is supported by most of the research into wage dynamics during the business cycle and by the <i>"wage curve"</i> of numerous countries. This  suggests that the demand for labour is independent of the real wages and so the price of labour (wages) is incapable of performing any  market clearing function. The supply and demand for labour are  determined by two different sets of factors. The relationship between wages and unemployment flows from the latter to the former rather than the reverse: the wage is influenced by the level of unemployment. Thus wages are not the product of a labour market which does not really exist but rather is the product of <i>"institutions, customs, privilege, social relations, history, law, and above all power, with an admixture of ingenuity and luck. But of course power, and particularly market or monopoly power, changes with the general of demand, the rate of growth, and the rate of unemployment. In periods of high employment, the weak gain on the strong; in periods of high unemployment, the strong gain on the weak."</i> [Galbraith, <b>Created Unequal</b>, p. 266]</p>
<p>This should be obvious enough. It is difficult for workers to resist  wage cuts and speeds-up when faced with the fear of mass unemployment. As such, higher rates of unemployment <i>"reduce labour's bargaining power  vis-a-vis business, and this helps explain why wages have declined and  workers have not received their share of productivity growth"</i> (between  1970 and 1993, only the top 20% of the US population increased its share  of national income). [Thomas I. Palley, <b>Plenty of Nothing</b>, p. 55  and p. 58] Strangely, though, this obvious fact seems lost on most economists.  In fact, if you took their arguments seriously then you would have to conclude that depressions and recessions are the periods during  which working class people do the best! This is on two levels. First, in neo-classical economics work is considered a disutility and  workers decide not to work at the market-clearing real wage because they prefer leisure to working. Leisure is assumed to be intrinsically good and the wage the means by which workers are encouraged to  sacrifice it. Thus high unemployment must be a good thing as it gives many more people leisure time. Second, for those in work their real wages are higher than before, so their income has risen. Alfred Marshall,  for example, argued that in depressions money wages fell but not as fast  as prices. A  <i>"powerful friction"</i> stopped this, which <i>"establish[ed] a higher  standard of living among the working classes"</i> and a <i>"diminish[ing of]  the inequalities of wealth."</i> When asked whether during a period of  depression the employed working classes got more than they did before,  he replied <i>"[m]ore than they did before, on the average."</i> [quoted by  Keynes, <b>Op. Cit.</b>, p. 396]</p>
<p>Thus, apparently, working class people do worse in booms than in slumps  and, moreover, they can resist wage cuts more in the face of mass  unemployment than in periods approaching full employment. That the  theory which produced these conclusions could be taken remotely  seriously shows the dangers of deducing an economic ideology from  a few simple axioms rather than trusting in empirical evidence and  common sense derived from experience. Nor should it come as too great a surprise, as "free market" capitalist economics tends to ignore  (or dismiss) the importance of economic power and the social context  within which individuals make their choices. As Bob Black acidly put  it with regards to the 1980s, it <i>"wasn't the <b>workers</b> who took these  gains [of increased productivity], not in higher wages, not in safer  working conditions, and not in shorter hours -- hours of work have  <b>increased</b> . . . It must be, then, that in the 80s and after workers  have 'chosen' lower wages, longer hours <b>and</b> greater danger on the  job. Yeah, sure."</i> [<i>"Smokestack Lightning,"</i> pp. 43-62, <b>Friendly Fire</b>,  p. 61]</p>
<p>In the real world, workers have little choice but to accept a job as  they have no independent means to exist in a pure capitalist system  and so no wages means no money for buying such trivialities as food  and shelter. The decision to take a job is, for most workers, a  non-decision -- paid work is undertaken out of economic necessity and  so we are not in a position to refuse work because real wages are too  low to be worth the effort (the welfare state reduces this pressure,  which is why the right and bosses are trying to destroy it). With high unemployment, pay and conditions will worsen while hours and  intensity of labour will increase as the fear of the sack will result  in increased job insecurity and so workers will be more willing to  placate their bosses by obeying and not complaining. Needless to  say, empirical evidence shows that <i>"when unemployment is  high, inequality rises. And when unemployment is low, inequality tends  to fall."</i> [James K. Galbraith, <b>Op. Cit.</b>, p. 148] This is unsurprising as the <i>"wage curve"</i> suggests that it is unemployment  which drives wage levels, not the other way round. This is important  as higher unemployment would therefore create higher inequality as  workers are in no position to claim back productivity increases and so wealth would flood upwards.</p>
<p>Then there is the issue of the backward-bending supply curve of labour we discussed at the end of the <a href="secC9.html#secc91">last section</a>. As the "labour market" is not really a market, cutting real wages will have the opposite effect on the supply of labour than its supporters claim. It is commonly found that as real wages fall, hours at work become longer and the number of workers in a family increases. This is because the labour supply curve is negatively slopped as families need to work more (i.e., provide more labour) to make ends meet. This means that a fall in real wages may <b>increase</b> the  supply of labour as workers are forced to work longer hours or take  second jobs simply to survive. The net effect of increasing supply  would be to <b>decrease</b> real wages even more and so, potentially, start a vicious circle and make the recession deeper. Looking at the US, we  find evidence that supports this analysis. As the wages for the bottom 80% of the population fell in real terms under Reagan and Bush in the 1980s, the  number of people with multiple jobs increased as did the number of mothers who  entered the labour market. In fact, <i>"the only reason that family income  was maintained is the massive increase in labour force participation of  married women . . . Put simply, jobs paying family wages have been disappearing,  and sustaining a family now requires that both adults work . . . The result has  been a squeeze on the amount of time that people have for themselves . . .  there is a loss of life quality associated with the decline in time for family  . . . they have also been forced to work longer . . . Americans are working  longer just to maintain their current position, and the quality of family life is likely declining. A time squeeze has therefore accompanied the wage  squeeze."</i> [Palley, <b>Op. Cit.</b>, pp. 63-4] That is, the supply of  labour <b>increased</b> as its price fell (Reagan's turn to military Keynesianism and incomplete nature of the "reforms" ensured that a deep spiral was avoided).</p>
<p>To understand why this is the case, it is necessary to think about how the  impact of eliminating the minimum wage and trade unions would actually have.  First, of course, there would be a drop in the wages of the poorest workers as the assertion is that the minimum wage increases unemployment by forcing wages up. The assertion is that the bosses would then employ more workers  as a result. However, this assumes that extra workers could easily be added  to the existing capital stock which may not be the case. Assuming this is  the case (and it <b>is</b> a big assumption), what happens to the workers who  have had their pay cut? Obviously, they still need to pay their bills which  means they either cut back on consumption and/or seek more work (assuming that prices have not fallen, as this would leave the real wage unchanged).  If the former happens, then firms may find that they face reduced demand  for their products and, consequently, have no need for the extra employees  predicted by the theory. If the latter happens, then the ranks of those  seeking work will increase as people look for extra jobs or people outside the labour market (like mothers and children) are forced into the job market. As  the supply of workers increase, wages <b>must</b> drop according to the logic of  the "free market" position. This does not mean that a recovery is impossible,  just that in the short and medium terms cutting wages will make a recession worse and be  unlikely to <b>reduce</b> unemployment for some time.</p>
<p>This suggests that a "free market" capitalism, marked by a fully competitive  labour market, no welfare programmes nor unemployment benefits, and extensive  business power to break unions and strikes would see aggregate demand  constantly rise and fall, in line with the business cycle, and unemployment  and inequality would follow suit. Moreover, unemployment would be higher  over most of the business cycle (and particularly at the bottom of the  slump) than under a capitalism with social programmes, militant unions  and legal rights to organise because the real wage would not be able to  stay at levels that could support aggregate demand nor could the  unemployed use their benefits to stimulate the production of consumer  goods. This suggests that a fully competitive labour market, as in the  19th century, would increase the instability of the system -- an  analysis which was confirmed in during the 1980s (<i>"the relationship  between measured inequality and economic stability . . . was weak but  if anything it suggests that the more egalitarian countries showed a  more stable pattern of growth after 1979."</i> [Dan Corry and Andrew Glyn, <i>"The Macroeconomics of equality, stability and growth"</i>, <b>Paying for Inequality</b>, Andrew Glyn and David Miliband (eds.) pp. 212-213]).</p>
<p>So, in summary, the available evidence suggests that <b>high</b> wages are  associated with <b>low</b> levels of unemployment. While this should be the expected result from any realistic analysis of the economic power which  marks capitalist economies, it does not provide much support for claims  that only by cutting real wages can unemployment be reduced. The "free  market" capitalist position and one based on reality have radically  different conclusions as well as political implications. Ultimately,  most laissez-faire economic analysis is unpersuasive both in terms of  the facts and their logic. While economics may be marked by axiomatic  reasoning which renders everything the markets does as optimal, the  problem is precisely that it is pure axiomatic reasoning with little or no  regard for the real world. Moreover, by some strange coincidence, they usually  involve policy implications which generally make the rich richer by  weakening the working class. Unsurprisingly, decades of empirical  evidence have not shifted the faith of those who think that the simple  axioms of economics take precedence over the real world nor has this faith lost its utility to the economically powerful.</p>
<h2><a name="secc93">C.9.3 Are "flexible" labour markets the answer to unemployment?</a></h2>
<p>The usual "free market" capitalist (or neo-liberal) argument is that labour  markets must become more "flexible" to solve the problem of unemployment.  This is done by weakening unions, reducing (or abolishing) the welfare  state, and so on. In defence of these policies, their proponents point to the low unemployment rates of the USA and UK and contrast them to the claimed economic woes of Europe (particularly France and Germany). As we will indicate in this section, this stance has more to do a touching  faith that deregulating the labour market brings the economy as a whole  closer to the ideal of "perfect competition" than a balanced analysis  and assessment of the available evidence. Moreover, it is always important to remember, as tenured economists (talking of protective labour market  institutions!) seem to forget, that deregulation can and does have high  economic (and not to mention individual and social) costs too.</p>
<p>The underlying argument for flexible labour markets is the notion that unemployment is cased by wages being too high and due to market imperfections wages are sticky downwards. While both claims, as we have seen above, are  dubious both factually and logically this has not stopped this position  becoming the reigning orthodoxy in elite circles. By market imperfections it is meant trade unions, laws which protect labour, unemployment benefit  and other forms of social welfare provision (and definitely <b>not</b>  big business, patent and copyright laws, or any other pro-business state interventions). All these ensure that wages for those employed are inflexible  downwards and the living standards of those unemployed are too high  to induce them to seek work. This means that orthodox economics is based  on (to use John Kenneth Galbraith's justly famous quip) the assumption that  the rich do not work because they are paid too little, while the poor do  not work because they are paid too much.</p>
<p>We should first point out that attacks on social welfare have a long pedigree and have been conducted with much the same rationale -- it made people lazy  and gave them flexibility when seeking work. For example, the British <b>Poor  Law Report</b> of the 1830s <i>"built its case against relief on the damage done  by poor relief to personal morality and labour discipline (much the same thing in the eyes of the commissioners)."</i> [David McNally, <b>Against the  Market</b>, p. 101] The report itself stated that <i>"the greatest evil"</i> of the  system was <i>"the spirit of laziness and insubordination that it creates."</i> [quoted by McNally, <b>Op. Cit.</b>, p. 101]</p>
<p>While the rhetoric used to justify attacks on welfare has changed somewhat  since then, the logic and rationale have not. They have as their root the  need to eliminate anything which provided working class people any means for independence from the labour market. It has always aimed to ensure that  the fear of the sack remains a powerful tool in the bosses arsenal and to ensure that their authority is not undermined. Ironically, therefore, its underlying aims are to <b>decrease</b> the options available to working class people, i.e. to reduce <b>our</b> flexibility within the labour market by  limiting our options to finding a job fast or face dire poverty (or worse).</p>
<p>Secondly, there is a unspoken paradox to this whole process. If we look at  the stated, public, rationale behind "flexibility" we find a strange  fact. While the labour market is to be made more "flexible" and in line  with ideal of "perfect competition", on the capitalist side no attempt is being made to bring <b>it</b> into line with that model. Let us not forget that perfect competition (the theoretical condition in which all resources, including labour, will be efficiently utilised) states that there must be a  large number of buyers and sellers. This is the case on the sellers side of  the "flexible" labour market, but this is <b>not</b> the case on the buyers  (where, as indicated in <a href="secC4.html">section C.4</a>, oligopoly reigns). Most who favour  labour market "flexibility" are also those most against the breaking up of  big business and oligopolistic markets or are against attempts to stop  mergers between dominant companies in and across markets. Yet the model  requires <b>both</b> sides to be made up of numerous small firms without market influence or power. So why expect making one side more "flexible" will  have a positive effect on the whole?</p>
<p>There is no logical reason for this to be the case and as we noted in  <a href="secC1.html#secc14">section C.1.4</a>, neo-classical economics agrees -- in an economy with both unions and big business, removing the former while retaining the latter will <b>not</b> bring it closer to the ideal of perfect competition. With  the resulting shift in power on the labour market things will get worse  as income is distributed from labour to capital. Which is, we must stress, precisely what <b>has</b> happened since the 1980s and the much lauded "reforms" of the labour market. It is a bit like expecting peace to occur between  two warring factions by disarming one side and arguing that because the  number of guns have been halved peacefulness has doubled! Of course, the  only "peace" that would result would be the peace of the graveyard or a  conquered people -- subservience can pass for peace, if you do not look  too close. In the end, calls for the "flexibility" of labour indicate the  truism that, under capitalism, labour exists to meet the requirements of  capital (or living labour exists to meet the needs of dead labour, a  truly insane way to organise a society).</p>
<p>Then there is the key question of comparing reality with the rhetoric. As economist Andrew Glyn points out, the neo-liberal orthodoxy on this issue <i>"has been strenuously promoted despite weak evidence for the magnitude of its benefits and in almost total neglect of its costs."</i>  In fact, <i>"there is no evidence that the countries which carried out  more reforms secured significant falls in unemployment."</i> This is perhaps  unsurprising as <i>"there is plenty of support for such deregulation from  business even without strong evidence that unemployment would be reduced."</i>  As far as welfare goes, the relationship between unemployment and benefits  is, if anything, in the 'wrong' direction (higher benefits do along with  lower unemployment). Of course there are a host of other influences on  unemployment but <i>"if benefits were very important we might expect <b>some</b>  degree of correlation in the 'right' (positive) direction . . . such a  lack of simple relation with unemployment applies to other likely suspects  such as employment protection and union membership."</i> [<b>Capitalism Unleashed</b>,  p. 48, p. 121, p. 48 and p. 47]</p>
<p>Nor is it mentioned that the history of labour market flexibility is somewhat  at odds with the theory. It is useful to remember that American unemployment  was far worse than Europe's during the 1950s, 60s and 70s. In fact, it did not  get better than the European average until the second half of the 1980s. [David  R. Howell, <i>"Introduction"</i>, pp. 3-34, <b>Fighting Unemployment</b>, David R. Howell  (ed.), pp. 10-11] To summarise:</p>
<blockquote><p> <i>"it appears to be only relatively recently that the maintained greater flexibility of US labour markets has apparently led to a superior performance in terms of lower unemployment, despite the fact this flexibility is no new phenomenon. Comparing, for example, the United States with the United  Kingdom, in the 1960s the United States averaged 4.8 per cent, with the  United Kingdom at 1.9 per cent; in the 1970s the United States rate rose  to 6.1 per cent, with the United Kingdom rising to 4.3 per cent, and it was  only in the 1980s that the ranking was reversed with the United States at  7.2 per cent and the United Kingdom at 10 per cent. . . Notice that this  reversal of rankings in the 1980s took place despite all the best efforts  of Mrs Thatcher to create labour market flexibility. . . [I]f labour market  flexibility is important in explaining the level of unemployment. . . why  does the level of unemployment remain so persistently high in a country,  Britain, where active measures have been taken to create flexibility?"</i>  [Keith Cowling and Roger Sugden, <b>Beyond Capitalism</b>, p. 9]
</p></blockquote>
<p>If we look at the fraction of the labour force without a job in America, we  find that in 1969 it was 3.4% (7.3% including the underemployed) and <b>rose</b>  to 6.1% in 1987 (16.8% including the underemployed). Using more recent data, we find that, on average, the unemployment rate was 6.2% in 1990-97 compared to 5.0% in the period 1950-65. In other words, labour market "flexibility" has not reduced unemployment levels, in fact "flexible" labour markets have been associated with higher levels of unemployment. Of course, we are comparing  different time periods. A lot changed between the 1960s and the 1990s and so comparing these periods cannot be the whole answer. However, it does seem strange that the period with stronger unions, higher minimum wages and more generous welfare state should be associated  with <b>lower</b> unemployment than the subsequent "flexible" period. It is  possible that the rise in flexibility and the increase in unemployment  may be unrelated. If we look at different countries over the same time  period we can see if "flexibility" actually reduces unemployment. As one  British economist notes, this may not be the case:</p>
<blockquote><p> <i>"Open unemployment is, of course, lower in the US. But once we allow for all forms of non-employment [such as underemployment, jobless workers who are not officially registered as such and so on], there is little difference between Europe and the US: between 1988 and 1994, 11 per cent of men aged 25-55 were not in work in France, compared with 13 per cent in the UK, 14 per cent in the US and 15 per cent in Germany."</i> [Richard Layard, quoted by John Gray, <b>False Dawn</b>, p. 113]
</p></blockquote>
<p>Also when evaluating the unemployment records of a country, other factors than the "official" rate given by the government must taken into account. Firstly, different governments have different definitions of what counts  as unemployment. As an example, the USA has a more restrictive definition  of who is unemployed than Germany. For example, in 2005 Germany's unemployment  rate was officially 11.2%. However, using the US definition it was only around  9% (7% in what was formerly West Germany). The offical figure was higher as  it included people, such as those involuntarily working part-time, as being  unemployed who are counted as being employed in the USA. America, in the  same year, had an unemployment rate of around 5%. So comparing unadjusted unemployment figures will give a radically different picture of the problem than using standardised ones. Sadly far too often business reporting in  newspapers fail to do this.</p>
<p>In addition, all estimates of America's unemployment record must take into account its incarceration rates. The prison population is  not counted as part of the labour force and so is excluded when  calculating unemployment figures. This is particularly significant as those in prison are disproportionately from demographic groups with  very high unemployment rates and so it is likely that a substantial  portion of these people would be unemployed if they were not in jail.  If America and the UK did not have the huge surge in prison population  since the 1980s neo-liberal reforms, the unemployment rate in both  countries would be significantly higher. In the late 1990s, for example, more than a million extra people would be seeking work if the US penal  policies resembled those of any other Western nation. [John Gray,  <b>Op. Cit.</b>, p. 113] England and Wales, unsurprisingly, tops the prison  league table for Western Europe. In 2005, 145 per 100,000 of their  population was incarcerated. In comparison, France had a rate of 88  while Germany had one of 97. This would, obviously, reduce the numbers  of those seeking work on the labour market and, consequently, reduce the unemployment statistics.</p>
<p>While the UK is praised for its "flexible" labour market in the 2000s,  many forget the price which was paid to achieve it and even more fail to realise that the figures hide a somewhat different reality. It is therefore essential to remember Britain's actual economic performance  during Thatcher's rule rather than the "economically correct" narrative  we have inherited from the media and economic "experts." When Thatcher  came to office in 1979 she did so promising to end the mass unemployment  experienced under Labour (which had doubled between 1974 and 1979).  Unemployment then tripled in her first term, rising to over 3 million  in 1982 (for the first time since the 1930s, representing 1 in 8 people). This was due in large part to the application of Monetarist dogma making  the recession far worse than it had to be. Unemployment remained at  record levels throughout the 1980s, only dropping to below its 1979 level in 1997 when New Labour took office. It gets worse. Faced with  unemployment rising to well over 10%, Thatcher's regime did what any  respectable government would -- it cooked the books. It changed how  unemployment was recorded in order to artificially lower the official  unemployment records. It also should be stressed that the UK unemployment figures do not take into account the Thatcherite policy of shunting as  many people as possible off the unemployment roles and onto sickness and incapacity  benefits during the 1980s and 1990s (<i>"In some countries, like the UK and  the Netherlands, many [of the unemployed] found their way onto sickness  benefit . . . Across the UK, for example, there was a strong positive  correlation between numbers on sickness benefits and the local unemployment  rate."</i> [Glyn, <b>Op. Cit.</b>, p. 107]). Once these "hidden" people are included the unemployment figures of Britain are similar to those  countries, such as France and Germany, who are more honest in recording who is and is not unemployed.</p>
<p>Eighteen years of high unemployment and a massive explosion in those on  incapacity benefits is hardly an advert for the benefits of "flexible" labour  market. However, a very deep recession, double-figure unemployment for  most of the decade, defeats for key strikes and unions plus continued  high unemployment for nearly two decades had an impact on the labour  movement. It made people willing to put up with anything in order to  remain in work. Hence Thatcher's "economic miracle" -- the working class  finally knew its place in the social hierarchy.</p>
<p>Thus, if a politician is elected who is hailed by the right as a "new Thatcher", i.e., seeking to "reform" the economy (which is "economically  correct" speak for using the state to break working class militancy) then there are some preconditions required before they force their populations down the road to (private) serfdom. They will have to triple unemployment in under three years and have such record levels  last over a decade, provoke the deepest recession since the 1930s,  oversee the destruction of the manufacturing sector and use the powers  of the state to break the mass protests and strikes their policies will  provoke. Whether they are successful depends on the willingness of  working class people to stand up for their liberties and rights and so  impose, from the streets, the changes that really needed  -- changes  that politicians will not, indeed cannot, achieve.</p>
<p>Nor should it be forgotten that here are many European countries with around  the same, or lower, official unemployment rates as the UK with much less  "flexible" labour markets. Taking the period 1983 to 1995, we find that  around 30 per cent of the population of OECD Europe lived in countries with  average unemployment rates lower than the USA and around 70 per cent in  countries with lower unemployment than Canada (whose wages are only  slightly less flexible than the USA). Furthermore, the European countries with the lowest unemployment rates were not noted for their labour market flexibility  (Austria 3.7%, Norway 4.1%, Portugal 6.4%, Sweden 3.9% and Switzerland 1.7%).  Britain, which probably had the most flexible labour market had an average  unemployment rate higher than half of Europe. And the unemployment rate of  Germany is heavily influenced by areas which were formally in East Germany.  Looking at the former West German regions only, unemployment between 1983  and 1995 was 6.3%, compared to 6.6% in the USA (and 9.8% in the UK). This  did not change subsequently. There are many regulated European countries  with lower unemployment than the USA (in 2002, 10 of 18 European countries  had lower unemployment rates). Thus:</p>
<blockquote><p> <i>"Often overlooked in the 1990s in the rush to embrace market fundamentalism  and to applaud the American model was the fact that several European countries  with strong welfare states consistently reported unemployment rates well below  that of the United States . . . At the same time, other European welfare sates,  characterised by some of the lowest levels of wage inequality and the highest  levels of social protection in the developed world, experienced substantial  declines in unemployment over the 1990s, reaching levels that are now below  that of the United States."</i> [David R. Howell, <i>"Conclusion"</i>, pp. 310-43,  <b>Op. Cit.</b>, p. 310]
</p></blockquote>
<p>As such, it is important to remember that <i>"the empirical basis"</i> of the  neo-liberal OECD-IMF orthodoxy is <i>"limited."</i> [Howell, <b>Op. Cit.</b>, p. 337]  In fact, the whole "Europe is in a state of decline" narrative which is used to justify the imposition of neo-liberal reforms there is better  understood as the corporate media's clever ploy to push Europe into the  hands of the self-destructing neo-liberalism that is slowly taking its  toll on Britain and America rather than a serious analysis of the real  situation there.</p>
<p>Take, for example, the issue of high youth unemployment in many European  countries which reached international awareness during the French anti-CPE  protests in 2006. In fact, the percentage of prime-age workers (25-54) in  employment is pretty similar in "regulated" France, Germany and Sweden as  in "flexible" America and Britain (it is much higher for women in Sweden).  However, there are significant differences in youth employment rates and  this suggests where the apparent unemployment problem lies in Europe. This  problem is due to the statistical method used to determine  the unemployment figures. The standard measure of unemployment divides the  number unemployed by the numbers unemployed plus employed. The flaw in  this should be obvious. For example, assume that 90% of French youths  are in education and of the remaining 10%, 5% are in work and 5% are  unemployed. This last 10% are the "labour force" and so we would get a  massive 50% unemployment rate but this is due to the low (5%) employment  rate. Looking at the youth population as a whole, only 5% are actually  unemployed. [David R. Howell, <i>"Introduction"</i>, pp. 3-34, <b>Op. Cit.</b>,  pp. 13-14] By the standard measure, French males age 15-24 had an unemployment  rate of 20.8% in 2007, as compared to 11.8% in America. Yet this  difference is mainly because, in France (as in the rest of Europe),  there are many more young males not in the labour force (more are in  school and fewer work part time while studying). As those who are not  in the labour market are not counted in the standard measure, this  gives an inflated value for youth unemployment. A far better comparison  would be to compare the number of unemployed divided by the population  of those in the same age group. This results in the USA having a rate  of 8.3% and France 8.6%.</p>
<p>Another source of the "decline" of Europe is usually linked to lower  GDP growth over the past few years compared to countries like Britain  and the USA. Yet this perspective fails to take into account internal  income distribution. Both the USA and UK are marked by large (and  increasing) inequality and that GDP growth is just as unequally  distributed. In America, for example, most of GDP growth since the 1980s has been captured by the top 5% of the population while median wages  have been (at best) flat. Ignoring the enrichment of the elite in the  USA and UK would mean that GDP growth would be, at least for the bulk  of the population, better in Europe. This means that while Europe may  have grown more slowly, it benefits more than just the ruling class.  Then there are such factors as poverty and social mobility. Rates of poverty are much worse in the neo-liberal countries, while social  mobility has fallen in the US and UK since the 1980s. There are less poor people in Europe and they stay in poverty for shorter periods of time compared to America and Britain.</p>
<p>Moreover, comparing Europe's income or GDP per person to the U.S. fails  to take into account the fact that Europeans work far less than Americans or British people. So while France may have lagged America in per capita income in 2007 ($30,693 to $43,144), it cannot be said that working class  people are automatically worse off as French workers have a significantly shorter working week and substantially more holidays. Less hours at work  and longer holidays may impact negatively on GDP but only an idiot would  say that this means the economy is worse, never mind the quality of life.   Economists, it should be remembered, cannot say that one person is worse  off than another if she has less income due to working fewer hours. So  GDP per capita may be  higher in the US, but only because American workers work more hours and  <b>not</b> because they are more productive. Like other Europeans, the French  have decided to work less and enjoy it more. So it is important to remember  that GDP is not synonymous with well-being and that inequality can produce misleading per capita income comparisons.</p>
<p>A far better indicator of economic welfare is productivity. It is understandable  that this is not used as a measure when comparing America to Europe as it is as  high, or higher, in France and other Western European countries as it is in the  US (and much higher than in the UK where low wages and long hours boost the  figure). And it should be remembered that rising productivity in the US  has not been reflecting in rising wages since 1980. The gains of  productivity, in other words, have been accumulated by the boss class  and not by the hard working American people (whose working week has  steadily increased during that period). Moreover, France created more  private sector jobs (+10% between 1996 and 2002, according to the OECD)  than the UK (+6%) or the US (+5%). Ironically, given the praise it  receives for being a neo-liberal model, the UK economy barely created  any net employment in the private sector between 2002 and 2007 (unemployment  <b>had</b> dropped, but that was due to increased state spending which led  to a large rise in public sector jobs).</p>
<p>Then there is the fact that some European countries <b>have</b> listened to the neo-liberal orthodoxy and reformed their markets but to little success. So it should be noted that <i>"there has in fact already been a very considerable liberalisation and reform in Europe,"</i> both in product  and labour markets. In fact, during the 1990s Germany and Italy reformed  their labour markets <i>"roughly ten times"</i> as much as the USA. The <i>"point  is that reforms should have boosted productivity growth in Europe,"</i> but  they did not. If regulation <i>"was the fundamental problem, some positive impact on labour productivity growth should have come already from the  very substantial deregulation already undertaken. Deregulation should  have contributed to an acceleration in productivity growth in Europe  whereas actually productivity growth declines. It is hard to see how  regulation, which was declining, could be the source of Europe's slowdown."</i> [Glyn, <b>Op. Cit.</b>, p. 144]</p>
<p>So, perhaps, "flexibility" is not the solution to unemployment some  claim it is (after all, the lack of a welfare state in the 19th century  did not stop mass unemployment nor long depressions occurring). Indeed, a  strong case can be made (and has been by left-wing economists) that the  higher open unemployment in Europe has a lot less to do with "rigid"  structures and "pampered" citizens than it does with the fiscal and  monetary austerity produced by the excessively tight monetary policies  of the European Central Bank plus the requirements of the Maastricht  Treaty and the <i>"Growth and Stability pact"</i> which aims to reduce demand  expansion (i.e. wage rises) under the name of price stability (i.e., the usual mantra of fighting inflation by lowering wage increases). So, <i>"[i]n the face of tight monetary policy imposed first by the [German]  Bundesbank and then by the European Central Bank . . . it has been  essential to keep wages moderate and budget deficits limited. With  domestic demand severely constrained, many European countries experiences particularly poor employment growth in the mid-1990s."</i> [David R. Howell, <i>"Conclusion"</i>, <b>Op. Cit.</b>, p. 337] This has been  essentially imposed by the EU bureaucrats onto the European population and as these policies, like the EU itself, has the support of most of  Europe's ruling class such an explanation is off the political agenda.</p>
<p>So if "flexibility" does not result in lower unemployment, just what  is it good for? The net results of American labour market "flexibility"  were summarised by head the US Federal Reserve Alan Greenspan in 1997.  He was discussing the late 1990s boom (which was, in fact, the product  of the dot.com bubble rather than the dawn of a new era so many claimed at the time). He explained why unemployment managed to fall below the  standard NAIRU rate without inflation increasing. In his words:</p>
<blockquote><p> <i>"Increases in hourly compensation . . . have continued to fall far short of what they would have been had historical relationships between compensation gains and the degree of labour market tightness held . . . As I see it, heightened job insecurity explains a  significant part of the restraint on compensation and the consequent  muted price inflation . . . The continued reluctance of workers to  leave their jobs to seek other employment as the labour market has  tightened provides further evidence of such concern, as does the  tendency toward longer labour union contracts . . . The low level  of work stoppages of recent years also attests to concern about job  security . . . The continued decline in the share of the private  workforce in labour unions has likely made wages more responsive to  market forces . . . Owing in part to the subdued behaviour of wages,  profits and rates of return on capital have risen to high levels."</i>  [quoted by Jim Stanford, <i>"Testing the Flexibility Paradigm: Canadian  Labor Market Performance in International Context,"</i> pp. 119-155,  <b>Fighting Unemployment</b>, David R. Howell (ed.), pp. 139-40]
</p></blockquote>
<p>Under such circumstances, it is obvious why unemployment could drop and inflation remain steady. Yet there is a massive contradiction in Greenspan's account. As well as showing how keen the Federal Reserve  investigates the state of the class struggle, ready to intervene when  the workers may be winning, it also suggests that flexibility works just one way:</p>
<blockquote><p> <i>"Some of the features highlighted by Greenspan reflect precisely a <b>lack</b> of flexibility in the labour market: a lack of response of compensation to tight labour markets, a reluctance of workers to leave their jobs, and the prevalence of long-term contracts that lock employment arrangements for six or more years at a time. And so Greenspan's portrayal of the unique features of the US model suggests that something more than flexibility is the key ingredient  at work -- or at least that 'flexibility' is being interpreted  once again from an unbalanced and one-sided perspective. It is, rather, a high degree of labour market <b>discipline</b> that seems to be the operative force. US workers remain insecure despite a  relatively low unemployment rate, and hence compensation gains  . . . were muted. This implies a consequent redistribution  of income from labour to capital . . . Greenspan's story is more about <b>fear</b> than it is about flexibility -- and hence this famous testimony has come to be known as Greenspan's 'fear factor'  hypothesis, in which he concisely described the importance of labour market discipline for his conduct of monetary policy."</i> [Jim Stanford, <b>Op. Cit.</b>, p. 140]
</p></blockquote>
<p>So while this attack on the wages, working conditions and social welfare is  conducted under the pre-Keynesian notion of wages being <i>"sticky"</i> downwards,  the underlying desire is to impose a "flexibility" which ensures that wages  are <i>"sticky"</i> <b>upwards.</b> This suggests a certain one-sidedness to the  "flexibility" of modern labour markets: employers enjoy the ability to  practice flexpoilation but the flexibility of workers to resist is reduced.</p>
<p>Rather than lack of "flexibility," the key factor in explaining high unemployment  in Europe is the anti-inflationary policies of its central banks, which pursue  high interest rates in order to "control" inflation (i.e. wages). In contrast, America has more flexibility simply due to the state of the working class there. With labour so effectively crushed in America, with so many workers  feeling they cannot change things or buying into the individualistic premises  of capitalism thanks to constant propaganda by business funded think-tanks,  the US central bank can rely on job insecurity and ideology to keep workers in their place in spite of relatively lower official unemployment. Meanwhile,  as the rich get richer many working class people spend their time making  ends meet and blaming everyone and everything but their ruling class for  their situation (<i>"US families must work even more hours to achieve the  standard of living their predecessors achieved 30 years ago."</i> [David R.  Howell, <i>"Conclusion"</i>, <b>Op. Cit.</b>, p. 338]).</p>
<p>All this is unsurprising for anarchists as we recognise that "flexibility"  just means weakening the bargaining power of labour in order to increase  the power and profits of the rich (hence the expression <i><b>"flexploitation"</b></i>!). Increased "flexibility" has been associated with <b>higher,</b> not lower  unemployment. This, again, is unsurprising, as a "flexible" labour market  basically means one in which workers are glad to have any job and face  increased insecurity at work (actually, <i><b>"insecurity"</b></i> would be a more honest  word to use to describe the ideal of a competitive labour market rather than  <i>"flexibility"</i> but such honesty would let the cat out of the bag). In such an  environment, workers' power is reduced meaning that capital gets a larger  share of the national income than labour and workers are less inclined to  stand up for their rights. This contributes to a fall in aggregate demand, so  increasing unemployment. In addition, we should note that "flexibility" may  have little effect on unemployment (although not on profits) as a reduction of  labour's bargaining power may result in <b>more</b> rather than less unemployment.  This is because firms can fire "excess" workers at will, increase the hours  of those who remain and stagnating or falling wages reduces  aggregate demand. Thus the paradox of increased "flexibility" resulting in  higher unemployment is only a paradox in the neo-classical framework. From  an anarchist perspective, it is just the way the system works as is the  paradox of overwork and unemployment occurring at the same time.</p>
<p>So while "free market" economics protrays unions as a form of market failure,  an interference with the natural workings of the market system and recommend  that the state should eliminate them or ensure that they are basically powerless to act, this simply does not reflect the real world. Any real economy is marked by the economic power of big business (in itself,  according to neo-classical economics, a distortion of the market).  Unless workers organise then they are in a weak position and will be even more exploited by their economic masters. Left-wing economist Thomas I. Palley presents the correct analysis of working class  organisation when he wrote:</p>
<blockquote><p><i> "The reality is that unions are a correction of market failure, namely the massive imbalance of power that exists between individual workers and corporate capital. The importance of labour market bargaining power for the distribution of income, means that unions are a fundamental prop for widespread prosperity. Weakening unions does not create a 'natural' market: it just creates a market in  which business has the power to dominate labour.<br>
</i></p>
<p><i>"The notion of perfect natural markets is built on the assumption that market participants have no power. In reality, the process of labour exchange is characterised not only by the presence of power, but also by gross inequality of power. An individual worker is at a great disadvantage in dealing with large corporations that have access to massive pools of capital and can organise in a fashion that renders every individual dispensible . . . Unions help rectify the imbalance of power in labour markets, and they therefore correct market failure rather than causing it."</i> <span style="font-weight: bold;">[</span><b>Op. Cit.</b>, pp. 36-7]</p>
</blockquote>
<p>The welfare state also increases the bargaining power of workers against their firms and limits the ability of firms to replace striking workers  with scabs. Given this, it is understandable why bosses hate unions and any state aid which undermines their economic power. Thus the <i>"hallmark"</i>  of the neo-liberal age <i>"is an economic environment that pits citizen  against citizen for the benefit of those who own and manage"</i> a country. [<b>Op. Cit</b>, p. 203]</p>
<p>And we must add that whenever governments have attempted to make the  labour market <i>"fully competitive"</i> it has either been the product of dictatorship (e.g. Chile under Pinochet) or occurred at the same time  as increased centralisation of state power and increased powers for the  police and employers (e.g. Britain under Thatcher, Reagan in the USA).  This is the agenda which is proscribed for Western Europe. In 2006,  when successful street protests stopped a proposed labour market  reform in France (the CPE), one American journalist, Elaine Sciolino,  complained that <i>"the government seems to fear its people; the people  seem to fear change."</i> [<b>New York Times</b>, March 17 2006] Such are  the contradictions of neo-liberalism. While proclaiming the need  to reduce state intervention, it requires increased state power to  impose its agenda. It needs to make people fear their government and  fear for their jobs. Once that has been achieved, then people who  accept "change" (i.e. the decisions of their economic, social and  political bosses) without question. That the French people do not want  a British or American style labour market, full of low-wage toilers  who serve at the boss's pleasure should not come as a surprise. Nor  should the notion that elected officials in a supposed democracy are  meant to reflect the feelings of the sovereign people be considered  as unusual or irrational.</p>
<p>The anti-democratic nature of capitalist "flexiblity" applies across the world. Latin American Presidents trying to introduce neo-liberalism into their countries have had to follow suit and <i>"ride roughshod over democratic institutions, using the tradition Latin American technique of governing by decree in order to bypass congressional opposition. . . Civil rights have also taken a battering. In Bolivia, the government attempted to defuse union opposition . . . by declaring a state of siege and imprisoning 143 strike leaders. . . In Colombia, the government used anti-terrorist legislation in 1993 to try 15 trade union leaders opposing the privatisation of the state telecommunications company. In the most extreme example, Peru's Alberto Fujimori dealt with a troublesome Congress by simply dissolving it . . . and seizing emergency powers."</i> [Duncan Green, <b>The Silent Revolution</b>, p. 157]</p>
<p>This is unsurprising. People, when left alone, will create communities,  organise together to collectively pursue their own happiness, protect  their communities and environment. In other words, they will form groups, associations and unions to control and influence the decisions that affect  them. In order to create a "fully competitive" labour market, individuals  must be atomised and unions, communities and associations weakened, if not  destroyed, in order to fully privatise life. State power must be used  to disempower the mass of the population, restrict their liberty, control popular organisations and social protest and so ensure that the free market  can function without opposition to the human suffering, misery and pain it would cause. People, to use Rousseau's evil term, <i>"must be forced  to be free."</i> And, unfortunately for neo-liberalism, the countries that tried to reform their labour market still suffered from high unemployment, plus increased social inequality and poverty and where still subject to the  booms and slumps of the business cycle.</p>
<p>Of course, bosses and the elite are hardly going to present their desire for higher profits and more power in those terms. Hence the need to appear concerned about the fate of the unemployed. As such, it is significant, of course, that right-wing economists only seem to become concerned over unemployment when trade unions are organising or politicians are thinking of introducing or raising the minimum wage. Then they will talk about how these will raise unemployment and harm workers, particularly those from ethnic minorities. Given that bosses  always oppose such policies, we must conclude that they are, in fact,  seeking a situation where there is full employment and finding willing  workers is hard to do. This seems, to say the least, an unlikely  situation. If bosses were convinced that, for example, raising the  minimum wage would increase unemployment rather than their wages bill  they would be supporting it wholeheartedly as it would allow them to  pressurise their workers into labouring longer and harder to remain in  employment. Suffice to say, bosses are in no hurry to see their pool of wage slaves drained and so their opposition to trade unions and  minimum wages are the product of need for profits rather than some concern for the unemployed.</p>
<p>This applies to family issues as well. In its support for "free markets"  you can get a taste of the schizophrenic  nature of the conservative right's approach to family values. On the one  hand, they complain that families do not spend enough time together as  they are under financial pressure and this results both parents going out  to work and working longer hours.  Families will also suffer because businesses do not have to offer paid  maternity leave, paid time off, flexitime, paid holidays, or other things  that benefit them. However, the right cannot bring themselves to advocate  unions and strike action by workers (or state intervention) to achieve  this. Ironically, their support for "free market" capitalism and  "individualism" undermines their support for "family values." Ultimately, that is because profits will always come before parents.</p>
<p>All this is unsurprising as, ultimately, the only real solution to unemployment  and overwork is to end wage labour and the liberation of humanity from the needs  of capital. Anarchists argue that an economy should exist to serve people rather  than people existing to serve the economy as under capitalism. This explains why  capitalism has always been marked by a focus on "what the economy wants" or  "what is best for the economy" as having a capitalist economy always results in  profit being placed over people. Thus we have the paradoxical situation, as  under neo-liberalism, where an economy is doing well while the bulk of the  population are not.</p>
<p>Finally, we must clarify the anarchist position on state welfare (we support  working class organisations, although we are critical of unions with bureaucratic  and top-down structures). As far as state welfare goes, anarchists do not place it high on the list of things we are struggling against (once the welfare  state for the rich has been abolished, then, perhaps, we will reconsider that). As we will discuss in <a href="secD1.html#secd15">section D.1.5</a>, anarchists are well aware that the current neo-liberal rhetoric of "minimising" the state is self-serving and hides an attack on the living standards of working class people. As such, we do not join in such attacks regardless of how critical we may be of aspects of the welfare state for we seek genuine reform  from below by those who use it rather than "reform" from above by politicians and bureaucrats in the interests of state and capital. We also seek to promote alternative social institutions which, unlike the welfare state, are under working class control and so cannot be cut by decree from above. For further discussion, see sections <a href="secJ5.html#secj515">J.5.15</a> and <a href="secJ5.html#secj516"> J.5.16</a>.</p>
<h2><a name="secc94">C.9.4 Is unemployment voluntary?</a></h2>
<p>Here we point out another aspect of the free market capitalist "blame the workers"  argument, of which the diatribes against unions and workers' rights highlighted  above is only a part. This is the assumption that unemployment is not involuntary  but is freely chosen by workers. As Nicholas Kaldor put it, for "free market"  economists involuntary employment <i>"cannot exist because it is excluded by the  assumptions."</i> [<b>Further Essays on Applied Economics</b>, p. x] Many  neo-classical economists claim that unemployed workers calculate that their  time is better spent searching for more highly paid employment (or living on  welfare than working) and so desire to be jobless. That this argument is taken  seriously says a lot about the state of modern capitalist economic theory, but  as it is popular in many right-wing circles, we should discuss it.</p>
<p>David Schweickart notes, these kinds of arguments ignore <i>"two well-established facts: First, when unemployment rises, it is layoffs, not [voluntary] quits,  that are rising. Second, unemployed workers normally accept their first job  offer. Neither of these facts fits well with the hypothesis that most  unemployment is a free choice of leisure."</i> [<b>Against Capitalism</b>, p. 108] When a company fires a number of its workers, it can hardly be said that the  sacked workers have calculated that their time is better spent looking for a  new job. They have no option. Of course, there are numerous jobs advertised  in the media. Does this not prove that capitalism always provides jobs for  those who want them? Hardly, as the number of jobs advertised must have some  correspondence to the number of unemployed and the required skills and those available. If 100 jobs are advertised in an areas reporting 1,000 unemployed,  it can scarcely be claimed that capitalism tends to full employment. This  hardly gives much support to the right-wing claim that unemployment is  "voluntary" and gives an obvious answer to right-wing economist Robert  Lucas's quest <i>"to explain why people allocate time to . . . unemployment,  we need to know why they prefer it to all other activities."</i> [quoted by  Schweickart, <b>Op. Cit.</b>, p. 108] A puzzle indeed! Perhaps this unworldly  perspective explains why there has been no real effort to verify the  assertion that unemployment is "voluntary leisure."</p>
<p>Somewhat ironically, given the desire for many on the right to deny the possibility of involuntary unemployment this perspective became increasingly influential at precisely the same time as the various theories of the  so-called "natural rate" of unemployment did (see <a href="secC9.html">section C.9</a>). Thus, at the same time as unemployment was proclaimed as being a "voluntary" choice economics was also implicitly arguing that this was nonsense, that unemployment  <b>is</b> an essential disciplinary tool within capitalism to keep workers in their  place (sorry, to fight inflation).</p>
<p>In addition, it is worthwhile to note that the right-wing assumption  that higher unemployment benefits and a healthy welfare state promote  unemployment is not supported by the evidence. As a moderate member  of the British Conservative Party notes, the <i>"OECD studied seventeen industrial countries and found no connect between a country's unemployment rate and the level of its social-security payments."</i> [<b>Dancing with Dogma</b>, p. 118] Moreover, the economists David Blanchflower and Andrew Oswald <i>"Wage Curve"</i> for many different countries is approximately the same for each of the fifteen countries they looked at. This also suggests that labour market unemployment is independent of social-security conditions as their "wage curve" can be considered as a measure of wage flexibility.  Both of these facts suggest that unemployment is involuntary in nature  and cutting social-security will <b>not</b> affect unemployment.</p>
<p>Another factor in considering the nature of unemployment is the effect of decades of "reform" of the welfare state conducted in both the USA and UK  since 1980. During the 1960s the welfare state was far more generous than  it was in the 1990s and unemployment was lower. If unemployment was  "voluntary" and due to social-security being high, we would expect a  decrease in unemployment as welfare was cut (this was, after all, the  rationale for cutting it in the first place). In fact, the reverse occurred,  with unemployment rising as the welfare state was cut. Lower social-security  payments did not lead to lower unemployment, quite the reverse in fact.</p>
<p>Faced with these facts, some may conclude that as unemployment is independent of social security payments then the welfare state can be cut. However, this  is not the case as the size of the welfare state does affect the poverty rates  and how long people remain in poverty. In the USA, the poverty rate was 11.7%  in 1979 and rose to 13% in 1988, and continued to rise to 15.1% in 1993. The  net effect of cutting the welfare state was to help <b>increase</b> poverty.  Similarly, in the UK during the same period, to quote the ex-Thatcherite  John Gray, there <i>"was the growth of an underclass. The percentage of British  (non-pensioner) households that are wholly workless -- that is, none of whose  members is active in the productive economy -- increased from 6.5 per cent in  1975 to 16.4 per cent in 1985 and 19.1 per cent in 1994. . . Between 1992  and 1997 there was a 15 per cent increase in unemployed lone parents. . .  This dramatic growth of an underclass occurred as a direct consequence of  neo-liberal welfare reforms, particularly as they affected housing."</i>  [<b>False Dawn</b>, p. 30] This is the opposite of the predictions of right-wing  theories and rhetoric.</p>
<p>As Gray correctly argues, the <i>"message of the American [and other] New  Right has always been that poverty and the under class are products of the  disincentive effects of welfare, not the free market."</i> He goes on to note  that it <i>"has never squared with the experience of the countries of  continental Europe where levels of welfare provision are far more  comprehensive than those of the United States have long co-existed with  the absence of anything resembling an American-style underclass. It does  not touch at virtually any point the experience of other Anglo-Saxon  countries."</i> He points to the example of New Zealand where <i>"the theories  of the American New Right achieved a rare and curious feat -- self-refutation  by their practical application. Contrary to the New Right's claims, the  abolition of nearly all universal social services and the stratification  of income groups for the purpose of targeting welfare benefits selectively  created a neo-liberal poverty trap."</i> [<b>Op. Cit.</b>, p. 42]</p>
<p>So while the level of unemployment benefits and the welfare state may  have little impact on the level of unemployment (which is to be expected  if the nature of unemployment is essentially involuntary), it <b>does</b> have  an effect on the nature, length and persistency of poverty. Cutting the welfare state increases poverty and the time spent in poverty  (and by cutting redistribution, it also increases inequality).</p>
<p>If we look at the relative size of a nation's social security transfers  as a percentage of Gross Domestic Product and its relative poverty rate  we find a correlation. Those nations with a high level of spending have  lower rates of poverty. In addition, there is a correlation between the spending level and the number of persistent poor. Those nations with high spending levels have more of their citizens escape poverty. For example, Sweden has a single-year poverty rate of 3% and a poverty escape rate of 45% and Germany has figures of 8% and 24% (and a persistent poverty rate of 2%). In contrast, the USA has figures of 20% and 15% (and a persistent poverty rate of 42%).</p>
<p>Given that a strong welfare state acts as a kind of floor under the  wage and working conditions of labour, it is easy to see why  capitalists and the supporters of "free market" capitalism seek to undermine it. By undermining the welfare state, by making labour "flexible," profits and power can be protected from working people standing up for their rights and interests. Little wonder the claimed benefits of "flexibility" have proved to be so elusive for the vast majority while inequality has exploded. The welfare state, in other words, reduces the attempts of the capitalist system to commodify labour and increases the options available to working class people. While it did not reduce the need to get a job, the welfare state did undermine  dependence on any particular employee and so increased workers'  independence and power. It is no coincidence that the attacks on unions  and the welfare state was and is framed in the rhetoric of protecting the  <i>"right of management to manage"</i> and of driving people back into wage  slavery. In other words, an attempt to increase the commodification of  labour by making work so insecure that workers will not stand up for  their rights.</p>
<p>Unemployment has tremendous social costs, with the unemployed facing financial  insecurity and the possibility of indebtedness and poverty. Many studies have  found that unemployment results in family distribution, ill health (both  physical and mental), suicide, drug addition, homelessness, malnutrition,  racial tensions and a host of other, negative, impacts. Given all this,  given the dire impact of joblessness, it strains belief that people would  <b>choose</b> to put themselves through it. The human costs of unemployment  are well documented. There is a stable correlation between rates of unemployment and the rates of mental-hospital admissions. There is a connection between unemployment and juvenile and young-adult crime. The effects on an individual's self-respect and the wider implications for their community and society are massive. As David  Schweickart concludes the <i>"costs of unemployment, whether measured in  terms of the cold cash of lost production and lost taxes or in the hotter  units of alienation, violence, and despair, are likely to be large under  Laissez Faire."</i> [<b>Op. Cit.</b>, p. 109]</p>
<p>Of course, it could be argued that the unemployed should look for work and leave their families, home towns, and communities in order to find it. However, this argument merely states that people should change their whole lives as required by "market forces" (and the wishes -- <i>"animal spirits,"</i> to use Keynes' term -- of those who own capital). In other words, it just acknowledges that capitalism results in people losing their ability to plan ahead and organise their lives (and that, in addition, it can deprive them of their sense of identity, dignity and self-respect as well), portraying this as somehow a requirement of life (or even, in some cases, noble).</p>
<p>It seems that capitalism is logically committed to viciously contravening the very values upon which it claims it be built, namely the respect for the innate worth and separateness of individuals. This is hardly surprising,  as capitalism is based on reducing individuals to the level of another  commodity (called "labour"). To requote Karl Polanyi:</p>
<blockquote><p> <i>"In human terms such a postulate [of a labour market] implied for the  worker extreme instability of earnings, utter absence of professional  standards, abject readiness to be shoved and pushed about indiscriminately,  complete dependence on the whims of the market. [Ludwig Von] Mises justly  argued that if workers 'did not act as trade unionists, but reduced their  demands and changed their locations and occupations according to the labour market, they would eventually find work.' This sums up the position under a system based on the postulate of the commodity character of labour. It is not for the commodity to decide where it should be offered for sale, to what purpose it should be used, at what price it should be allowed to change hands, and in what manner it should be consumed or destroyed."</i>  [<b>The Great Transformation</b>, p. 176]
</p></blockquote>
<p>However, people are <b>not</b> commodities but living, thinking, feeling individuals. The "labour market" is more a social institution than an economic one and people and work more than mere commodities. If we reject the neo-liberals' assumptions for the nonsense they are, their case fails. Capitalism, ultimately, cannot provide full employment simply because labour is <b>not</b> a commodity (and as we discussed in <a href="secC7.html">section C.7</a>, this revolt against commodification is a key part of understanding the business cycle and so unemployment).</p>
  <div id="book-navigation-239" class="book-navigation">

        <div class="page-links clear-block">
              <a href="secC8.html" class="page-previous" title="Go to previous page">‹ C.8 Is state control of credit the cause of the business cycle?</a>
                    <a href="secCcon.html" class="page-up" title="Go to parent page">up</a>
                    <a href="secC10.html" class="page-next" title="Go to next page">C.10 Is "free market" capitalism the best way to reduce poverty? ›</a>
          </div>

  </div>
  </div>
  </body>
</html>